Free Essay

Aristotle and Descartes

In:

Submitted By frederichenry
Words 8048
Pages 33
Two Views of Soul:
Aristotle and Descartes*
THEODORE TRACY, SJ.
What first attracted my interest to a possible comparison was the realization that, unlike Plato, both Aristotle and Descartes shared the view that, first, there is but a single soul and, second, that this soul operates principally through a single specific bodily organ. Given his own understanding, I believe Descartes could agree totally with
Aristotle's statement that the soul's "essential nature cannot be
* This paper was originally presented at the University of South Carolina in April
1981' as a contribution to a symposium on "Soul and Mind in Ancient Philosophy," organized by Professor Rosamond Kent Sprague.
248 Illinois Classical Studies, XI corporeal; yet it is also clear that soul is present in a particular bodily part, and this one of the parts having control over the rest":' dfiXou 6ri ovx oihv r' tivai adua rffv ovtriau ocvrfiq, aW 5fi(t)c, Sri 7' iv tlvl tov
(TUifiaToq inrapxii^ nopiw (t>avtpbv, kcu iv tovtw tivi twv ixovruiv bvvafiiv eV roJq nopioic,. {Parva Naturalia 467b 13- 16)
For Aristotle, as we know, that particular controlling organ is the heart. In his treatise On Memory, for example, Aristotle declares that in animals, including man, "the source and control center
{otpxvY of both the sensitive and nutritive soul must be in the heart": apayKT) Koi rrfc, ataQr]TiKr\c, kou rriq dpeirTLKfic, ^vxri<i ^v ry Kapb'ux rffv otpxw etW. {PN 469a5-7)
Again, in the De Partibus Animalium, the heart is designated as the control center of sense perception and emotional response: "For it is in the front and center of the body that the heart is situated, in which we say is the source and control center of life and of all motion and sensation": f; p.lv yap Kapbia iv roiq tp.irpoaQev koll ev neaui Ketrm, iv y Trjv apxw <t>citi^v
T^q ^(iirfc, Kot iraar^q Kivr^aedq, re koi aLcrdrjaeojq. {De Partibus Animalium
665all-13)
Later, Aristotle adds: "Moreover, the motions of pain and pleasure, and generally of all sensation, plainly have their source in the heart, and find in it their ultimate termination": en 6' ai Kivr}(TeL<; rdv ifbeoiv Koi rdv XvinijpCiiv Koi Skuiq iraar^q aiadfjaeuq evrevdep apxbfieuai (j>aiuovTai Koi irpbc, ravrrju irepaivovaai. (666al2-13)
In the De Anima, in a context emphasizing the bodily aspects of psychic states, Aristotle specifies: "... We may regard anger or fear
' The following are the sources for the text of the Greek, French and Latin passages quoted. From Aristotle: De Anima, edited with introduction and commentary by Sir David Ross (Oxford 1961); Parva Naturalia, edited with introduction and commentary by Sir David Ross (Oxford 1957); De Generatione Animalium {Generation of Animals, with an English translation, by A. L. Peck [Cambridge, Mass. 1953]); De
Partibus Animalium {Parts of Animals, with an English translation, by A. L. Peck
[Cambridge, Mass. 1955]); De Motu Animalium, with translation, commentary, and essays by Martha Craven Nussbaum (Princeton 1978). From Descartes: Oeuvres de
Descartes, publiees par Charles Adam et Paul Tannery (Paris 1899) (= A-T).
The translations from Aristotle are adapted from Ross, Peck and Nussbaum, and in the case of the De Anima from R. D. Hicks, Aristotle: De Anima (Cambridge 1907).
The translations from Descartes are from The Philosophical Works ofDescartes, rendered into English by E. S. Haldane and G. R. T. Ross, 2 vols. (Cambridge 1967) (= H-R).
^ On the notion of 17 dpxv as "source and control center," see Metaphysics
1012b34-1013aI4.
Theodore Tracy, SJ. 249 as such and such movements of the heart, and thinking (dLauoeiadai) as such and such another movement of that organ. . .
."^
. . . oiov TO opyi^taOai rj (f>o0€ladai to tt^v Kapbuxv wSl KivetaOai, to 81 biavodadai fj Ti TOiovTOv ujooq rj erepov ti. . . . (408b8-9).
Clearly, then, for Aristotle the psychic functions of sense perception, consciousness of pleasure and pain, emotional response, initiation of external movement, even thinking or reasoning (diauoeladai) are centered in the heart, the control center of the human organism.
For Descartes, the soul is principally present in, and operates through, the pineal gland, which he situates inside the cavity of the brain. In his treatise On the Passions of the Soul, for example, describing how soul and body act on one another, Descartes begins: "Let us then conceive here that the soul has its principal seat {son siege principal) in the little gland which exists in the middle of the brain"
("Concevons done icy que I'ame a son siege principal dans la petite glande qui est au milieu du cerveau . . .", Passions, Art. XXIV; H-R
I, 347; A-T XI, 354). Again, he refers to the pineal as "the small gland which is the main seat of the soul" (". . . la petite glande qui est le principal siege de I'ame, . . ." ibid.) and maintains that "the soul cannot have any other seat in all the body than this gland wherein to exercise its functions immediately" (". . . I'ame ne pent avoir en tout le corps aucun autre lieu que cette glande, ou elle exerce immediatement ses fonctions, . . ." Passions, Art. XXXII; H-R I, 346;
A-T XI, 352).
A closer examination of the psychology of both Aristotle and
Descartes reveals, of course, that neither conceived the soul as locally confined to a single organ, but united with the entire body. In the De
Aninia, you recall, Aristotle defines soul as "the first actuality of a natural body furnished with organs:" ej/reXexeia T? TrpcoTTj aic^iaTOc, <f)vatK0v opyauiKOV (412b5-6).
Then, after comparing the unity of soul and body to that of eyesight and eye, he continues: "What has been said of the part must be understood to apply to the whole living body; for as sensation of a part of the body is to that part, so is sensation as a whole to the whole sentient body as such": del 8fi Xa^elv to (ttI nepovq e'<^' SKov tov ^uiPToq aCinaTOc,. avaXoyov yap ex«i wq TO nepoq irpbc, to fiepoq, ovtojc, t; 5\ri aiad-qau; irpbq to SKov adfia to oacevTLKbu, ^ TOIOVTOV. (412522-25; cf. 4 14a 14- 19)
Since the soul is the first actuality of a natural body furnished with
' Oxford translation, and cf. Hicks, p. 274 ad b9; also 403a31, 432b31.
250 Illinois Classical Studies, XI organs, however, it can be conceived to be especially present and operating in a principal or controlling organ of the body, as is the case for the heart in Aristotle's psychology.
Likewise, Descartes maintains clearly that the soul is really joined to the whole body, and ... we cannot, properly speaking, say that it exists in any one of its parts to the exclusion of the others, because it is one and in some manner indivisible.
. . . fame est veritablement jointe a tout le corps, & ... on ne peut pas proprement dire qu'elle soit en quelcune de ses parties, a I'exclusion des autres, a cause qu'il est un, & en quelque fa^on indivisible
.. . {Passions, Art. XXX; H-R I, 345; A-T XI, 351).
However, he also maintains:
It is likewise necessary to know that although the soul is joined to the whole body, there is yet in that a certain part in which it exercises its functions more particularly than in all the others. . . .
II est besoin aussi de sgavoir que, bien que I'ame soit jointe a tout le corps, il y a neantmoins en luy quelque partie, en laquelle elle exerce ses fonctions plus particulierement qu'en toutes les autres. {Passions,
Art. XXXI; H-R I, 345; A-T XI, 351-52)
That part is, of course, the pineal gland.
How do Aristotle and Descartes conceive the soul as operating especially in or through this central organ? The process is, of course, far too complex for detailed description here. However, the sensorymotor mechanism in Descartes can be summarized broadly in his own words as follows:
Let us then conceive here that the soul has its principal seat in the little gland which exists in the middle of the brain, from whence it radiates forth through all the remainder of the body by means of the animal spirits, nerves, and even the blood. . . .
Concevons done icy que fame a son siege principal dans la petite glande qui est au milieu du cerveau, d'ou elle rayonne en tout le reste du corps par I'entremise des esprits, des nerfs, & mesme du sang. . . .
{Passions, Art. XXXIV; H-R I, 347; A-T XI, 354)
This gives us the general structure. He then provides for reflex or instinctive reaction as follows:
And recollecting what has been said about the machine of our body,
i.e., that the little filaments of our nerves are so distributed in all its parts that on the occasion of the diverse movements which are there excited by sensible objects, they open in diverse ways the pores of the brain, which causes the animal spirits contained in these cavities to enter in diverse ways into the muscles. . . .
Theodore Tracy, SJ. 251
Et nous souvenant de ce qui a este dit cy-dessus de la machine de nostre corps, a sgavoir que les petits filets de nos nerfs sont tellement distribuez en toutes se parties, qu'a I'occasion des divers mouvemens qui y sont excitez par les objets sensibles, ils ouvrent diversement les pores du cerveau, ce qui fait que les esprits animaux contenus en ses cavitez entrent diversement dans les muscles. . . . {Pass. XXXIV; H-R
I, 347; A-T XI, 354)
Sense perceptions from external and internal stimuli are accounted for thus:
... let us here add that the small gland which is the main seat of the soul is so suspended between the cavities [of the brain] which contain • the [animal] spirits that it can be moved by them in as many different ways as there are sensible diversities in the object; but that it may also be moved in diverse ways by the soul whose nature is such that it receives in itself as many diverse impressions,—that is to say, that it possesses as many diverse perceptions as there are diverse movements in this gland.
Adjoustons icy que la petite glande qui est le principal siege de I'ame, est tellement suspendue entre les cavitez qui contienent ces esprits, qu'elle peut estre meue par eux en autant de diverses famous, qu'il y a de diversitez sensibles dans les objets; mais qu'elle peut aussi estro» diversement meue par I'ame, laquelle est de telle nature qu'elle recoit autant de diverses impressions en elle, c'est a dire, qu'elle a autant de diverses perceptions, qu'il arrive de divers mouvemens en cette glande.
(Pass. XXXIV; H-R I, 347; A-T XI, 254-55)
Motor responses are provided for as follows:
Reciprocally, likewise, the machine of the body is so formed that from the simple fact that this gland is diversely moved by the soul ... it thrusts the [animal] spirits which surround it towards the pores of the brain, which conduct them by the nerves into the muscles, by which means it causes them to move the limbs.
Comme aussi reciproquement la machine du corps est tellement composee, que de cela seul que cette glande est diversement meue par I'ame . . . elle pousse les esprits qui I'environnent vers les pores du cerveau, qui les conduisent par les nerfs dans les muscles, au moyen de quoy elle leur fait mouvoir les membres. {Pass. XXXIV; H-R I,
347; A-T XI, 355)
The process is that sense impulses, transmitted through the nerves, are mediated by "animal spirits" to the pineal gland, where they cause the conscious experience of sense perception in the soul.
Likewise, the soul can move the pineal gland, setting up movement of the surrounding "animal spirits" which is thus transmitted to nerves and muscles as motor impulses.
252 Illinois Classical Studies, XI
In this the critical role of the pineal gland and what Descartes calls
"animal spirits" must be evident. He goes on to describe how the visual perception of an object takes place through images in the optic nerves ultimately transmitted by the animal spirits in the surrounding brain cavities to the pineal gland which, he says, "acting immediately upon the soul, causes it to see" ("agissant immediatement contre
I'ame, luy fait voir. . . ," Passions, Art. XXXV; H-R I, 347-48; A-T
XI, 356). Awareness of interior passion also,—fear, for example— comes about by reaction of the animal spirits "to give movement to the gland by which fear is placed in the soul" ("donner le mouvement a la glande, par lequel la peur est mise dans I'ame . . . ," Passions, Art.
XXXVIII; H-R I, 349; A-T XI, 358).
Descartes conceives these animal spirits as "a certain very subtle air or wind" (". . . un certain air ou vent tres-subtil, qu'on nomme les esprits animaux . . . ," Passions, Art. VII; H-R I, 334; A-T XI,
332); and again, "material bodies of extreme minuteness. . . . they move very quickly like the particles of the flame which issues from a torch" (". . . ce sont des corps tres-petits, & qui se meuvent tresviste, ainsi que les parties de la flame qui sort d'un flambeau . . . ,"
Passiotis, Art. X; H-R I, 336; A-T XI, 335); elsewhere, "a very subtle wind, or rather a flame which is very pure and very vivid" (". . . un vent tres subtil, ou plutost comme une flame tres pure 8c tres vive . . . ,"
Discourse on Method V; H-R I, 115; A-T VI, 54). He explains that animal spirits are the product of "the most animated and subtle portions of the blood which the heat has rarefied in the heart"
(". . . les plus vives & plus subtiles parties du sang, que la chaleur a rarefiees dans le coeur. . .") and sent up to fill the cavities of the brain {Passions, Art. X; H-R I, 335; A-T XI, 334). Incidentally,
Descartes, like Aristotle, considers the heart to be the center of vital heat in the body. He says that so long as we live there is a continual heat in our heart ... a species of fire which the blood of the veins maintains, and . . . this fire is the corporeal principle of all the movements of our members.
. . . pendant que nous vivons, il y a une chaleur continuelle en nostre coeur, . . . une espece de feu que le sang des venes y entretient, & . . . ce feu est le principe corporel de tous le mouvemens de nos membres.
{Passions, Art. VIII; H-R I, 335; A-T XI, 333)
Descartes' "animal spirits" reminds us immediately of the mysterious
(TVn<t)VTov TTVivna—the "connate spirit" or "breath"—which is for Aristotle the principal medium by which the soul present in the heart is affected by sensory impulses and emotional reactions, and by which it initiates external response. Like Descartes' "animal spirits,"
Theodore Tracy, S.J. 253 the avn<i>VTov Tvevfia, as the term implies, is a kind of breath or air; but warm air, involving an element of heat that is, as Aristotle says,
"analogous to the element of the stars" {avaXoyou ovcra to) tcop a<TTpo)v oTOLX^io), De Gen. Animalium 736b38-737al), giving it special capacities for the communication of life and vital functions {ibid.
736b30 ff.r
As Descartes' animal spirits surround the pineal gland, so Aristotle's avn4>vTou TTvevixa operates within and around the heart especially, which at one point he calls the "pneumatic member" (fTri to)
TTvev/xaTLKO) ixopio), De Gen. An. 781a31). The avyi(t)VTov Trvev/xa mediates sensory impulses coming from the sense organ to the soul present in the heart (e.g., De Gen. An. 781a21-33); and mediates motor impulses from the soul in the heart to the joints and sinews. Aristotle says:
All animals both possess symphyton pneuma and derive their strength from this. . . . This [pneuma] seems to bear a relation to the soul-assource similar to that which the point in the joints,—the one which imparts movement and is itself moved—has to the unmoved. And since the soul-source is . . . situated in the heart, it is clear that the symphyton pneuma is also there" {De Motu An. 703a9-16 Nussbaum, adapted). iravra 81 <f)aiveTai tu foia koI (Xovtu Trvevfia (Tvn(f)VTOv koo. Cax^ovTa
TOVTW. . . . Tovro de irpoq tt) apxw ttiv ypvxt-KriP toiKtv op^ioiq ex^iv o)(nrtp to iv
Talc, Katiiralc, ar\peiov, to kivovv kou. uvovpevov, Trpbq to akivrjTov. eiret 6' i] apxv
Tolc, pev iv Ty Kapb'ux . . . 5ia tovto koI to irvevpa to avp4>VT0V ivTovda (jyaivtTai
Sv.
Thus in Aristotle the avpcjyvTov Trvevpa functions as immediate agent of the life processes originating in the soul operating through the heart. The details can be found summarized elsewhere.^ I only mean to suggest here that there seems to be a close analogy between
Descartes' "animal spirits" and Aristotle's avpcpvTov irvivpa with relation to the central organ (pineal gland or heart) through which soul principally operates. Although Descartes' knowledge of anatomy and physiology, especially that of the central nervous system, represents a considerable advance over Aristotle, when it comes to explaining the body-soul relationship he is still left with Aristotle's basic model: soul operating in a central organ through the medium of a
^ M. Nussbaum, Aristotle's De Motu Animalium (Princeton 1978), p. 162: "We can only say that pneuma is, apparently, air with a special kind of heat in it that makes it behave unlike ordinary air, more like a different element."
' See A. L. Peck's De. Gen. An. in the Loeb Series (1953), Appendix B, 576-93;
F. Solmsen,/ of Hellenic Studies 77 (1957), 119-23; M. Nussbaum, 143-164 (Essay
3).
254 Illinois Classical Studies, XI special subtle kind of matter (a warm air). He sums up the process as follows:
Hence in our very selves the mind [or soul] by no means moves the external limbs immediately, but merely directs the subtle fluid, styled the animal spirits, that passes from the heart through the brain toward the muscles, and determines this fluid to perform definite motions, these animal spirits being in their own nature capable of being utilized with equal facility for many distinct actions.
. . . adeo ut nequidem in nobis ipsis mens immediate moveat membra externa, sed dirigat tantum spiritus a corde per cerebrum in musculos fluentes eosque ad certos motus determinet, cum ex se isti spiritus ad multas actiones diversas aeque facile applicentur. {Reply to Objections
IV, H-R II, 103; A-T VII, 229)
Despite these superficial similarities in their psychology, however,
Descartes' view of soul differs radically from that of Aristotle. There is little need to remind this audience of the implications of Aristotle's hylomorphic view of soul and body as developed in the De Anima especially, where the relationship is that of form to matter in constituting the living individual organism; where soul is ''the first actuation
{ivTeX(x^La) of a natural body furnished with organs" {evreXix^La i)
-KpiOTt] (TixiixaToc, (pvaLKov opyauLKov, De An. 412b5), and where all second actuations (even some noetic) are adequately described only as events of the body-soul compound, having both psychic and somatic aspects.
As Aristotle explains, when the person experiences anger,, tenderness, fear, pity, courage, joy, loving, hating, even thought "... simultaneously with these the body is modified in some way" {oi^a yap
TovToiq Traaxei ri to a(cp.a, De An. 403a 18). The unity between body and soul, matter and form, is as close in the living compound as that of wax and the impression in the wax; the axe and axeness; the eye and the power of sight {ibid. 412b6-413a3). A material eye without sight is no more an eye than a corpse is a man {De Gen. An. 735a7-8; and cf. 734b25-27, 726b23-25).'^ Body and soul are simply two inseparable aspects of the living organism.
The same kind of unity exists, by implication, between the psychic and somatic aspects of all second actuations as well. For Aristotle maintains that it is as inadequate to describe the experience of anger simply as "the desire for retaliation" (6 ixkv yap ope^Lv auTLXvirrjaeo^q, its formal aspect) as it would be to describe it simply as "a boiling of the blood around the heart" (6 de ^eciv tov irtpX Kapbiav aifiaToq, its
'' "No part of the body will be such in more than name unless it has some Soul in it (e.g. the eye of a dead person)" {ovn nopiov earai ^lr) fifrixou [4^XV<i] otXk' tj b^ujivvntjii;,, wairep redviwroc, oipdaXpcx;). A. L. Peck, De Gen. An. 735a7-8.
Theodore Tracy, S.J. 255
But Aristotle goes beyond this, as you recall, to describe the soul, once implanted and joined to appropriate matter, also as efficient cause in the development and maintenance of organs and life functions in the individual. The De Generatione Animalium details the process by which the implanted soul forms the heart first, and thereafter the rest of the organs as outgrowths and extensions from the heart
(742a 16 ff.). The De Anima generalizes on this:
Moreover, the soul is also the origin of motion from place to place. . . . Qualitative change also, and growth are due to soul. For sensation is supposed to be a sort of qualitative change. . . . The same holds of growth and decay. ... aXKa nfjv Koi ddev irpCyrov i] Kara rbirov Kivrjcnq, ^I'VXV- • • ecTi de kol aXKoiuiaiq
Koi av^rjaiq Kara ypvxw- v fiev yap ataOijaic, aXKomaiq tk; uvai boKtl. . . . onoiuic, 8e Kot TTcpt ocv^ifaewq re Koi (f>diaiU3q Ixti. {De An. 415b21-26)
In the De Anima and elsewhere Aristotle describes both psychic and somatic aspects of the nutritive, sentient, movent, and desiderative functions in man. But when he comes to grips with the problem of man's highest function, the intellectual, his hylomorphic account breaks down,—at least to the extent that one so-called "part" of the soul, the intellect {vovq: the power of comprehending non-material reality), is denied a specific bodily organ:
If the entire soul holds together the whole body, then each of its
"parts" ought properly to hold together some part of the body. But this seems impossible. For it is difficult to conjecture what part the intellect will hold together or how it can hold any part together. a yap rj Skt] ypvxn i^btv to aobfia avvexei, irpoariKei koi tu}v piopioiv tKaarov avv'tx^LV Ti Tov aConaroq. tovto 5' eoiKev advvaTU}- iroiov yap nbpiov rf -KUiq b vovq avvi^H, xoi^^TTov Kal irXaaaL. {De An. 4 11 bl 5- 18)
When he comes to analyze the intellectual function closely, however
{De An. 429a 10 ff.), Aristotle distinguishes two "parts" of intellect:
(1) the receptive intellect, the potentiality for receiving the intelligible forms transmitted in the phantasms, and (2) the activating or agent intellect, which actuates this potency "as light brings out the colors present in a darkened room" {tpottov yap Tiva koL to ^ox; ttouX to. hvva.n€L ovra xP^I-*^<XTa evepyeia xP<J^I^<^TOi> De An. 430a 15- 17). The receptive intellect is apparently closely involved with those faculties of soul that inform and operate through a material organ, namely, the central sense power, ^ai/raata, and memory, operating in the heart. The agent intellect alone seems to actuate no material organ, which implies for Aristotle that it actuates itself as pure form or act.
Consequently it is capable of separate existence, for any "part" of
256 Illinois Classical Studies, XI heart. The agent intellect alone seems to actuate no material organ, which implies for Aristotle that it actuates itself as pure form or act.
Consequently it is capable of separate existence, for any "part" of soul not actuating material body is separable (De An. 413a3-6).
Aristotle must have this aspect of vovq in mind when he says:
It would seem to be a distinct species of soul, alone capable of separate existence, something eternal (aidiov), as it were, distinct from the perishable. a\X' (OLKe \pvxv<i y^voc, erepov eivm, Koi tovto nbvov ivSex^adai X'*'Ptf«o'^«i.
Kadairep to oilbiov tov (t>6apT0v. {De An. 413b25-27)
If this "part" of the intellectual soul is eternal, it must have preexisted before the individual human organism was conceived.
Aristotle seems to have accepted this consequence, but is vague about the manner of its joining the compound, explaining that while the nutritive and sentient "souls" with potentiality for the rational are supplied by the parents, the nous alone enters, in addition, from outside and is alone divine; for bodily activity has no share in its activity.
XeiireraL dfi tov vovv hovov dvpadiv eTreiauvai Koi detov eivai nbvov. ovdev yap ocvTOV Ty ivepyeia KOivoivd aoinaTiKT} ivepyeia. {De Gen. An. 736b27-29)
Likewise, since this activating povq is eternal, it must survive the dissolution of the compound at death.
But nous seems to be engendered in us as a self-existing substance, and to be imperishable.
6 5e vovc, wiKtv iyyiveadm ovaia tic, ovaa, koi ov (t>9€ip€adai. {De An.
408b 18- 19)
Hence Aristotle does affirm the immortality of this part of soul. But this seems in no way to constitute personal immortality. For Aristotle asserts that reasoning, love, and hatred are not attributes of the nous but of its individual possessor. . . . Hence, when this possessor perishes, there is neither memory or love; for these never did belong to the nous but to the composite whole which has perished; while the nous is doubtless a thing more divine and impassive.
TO 5i biavodadm Koi (fnXetu rj fuaeiv om tOTw iKOVov [vov\ iradri, aWa tovSI
TOV exovToq Ikhvo. . . .bio Kcii tovtov (f>daponevov ovt( p.VT]px)v(va oirre (JkXhov yap (Kfivov rju, aXXa tov kolvov, o airbXuXev. b bi vovc, ixrox, daintpov n Koi airaSeq eaTLv. {De An. 408b25-29)
Even the receptive nous perishes with memory:
Theodore Tracy, SJ. 257
. . . TOVTO nbvop ccdavaTov kcu ciihov {ov nvrjuovtvonep 8e, 5ti. tovto fiev airade;, b be iraOriTiKoq povq <f>6apTb(;y koi avev tovtov ovdep poet. {ibid.
430a23-25)
The surviving soul is pure act, independent of matter and selfexistent, without memory of previous existence, without acquired knowledge or modification of any sort (airadeq) resulting from its operation in the living individual. This is hardly personal immortality.
On the other hand, one of the propositions that Descartes considers most important to establish is precisely the proposition that the personal soul is immortal. His Discourse on the Method indicates that his whole discussion of the human soul is linked with the problem of its origin and destiny. He claims to have shown that the rational soul
"could not be in any way derived from the power of matter. . . but that it must be expressly created" (". . . ne peut aucunement estre tiree de la puissance de la matiere, . . . mais qu'elle doit expressement estre creee" . . . , Disc. V; H-R I, 118; A-T VI, 59-60). And again,
"that our soul is in its nature entirely independent of body, and in consequence that it is not liable to die with it" (". . . la nostre [ame] est d'une nature entierement independante du cors, & par consequent, qu'elle n'est point suiette a mourir avec luy. . . , Disc. V, end; H-R I,
118; A-T VI, 59-60; cf. dedication to the Meditations, H-R I, 333*34;
Med. II).
Descartes begins his search for truth, as you recall, not with
Aristotle's attempt at objective analysis of the external universe, of living beings, and of man in the total scheme of things, but modo geometrico, with a clear, distinct, and undeniable proposition drawn from inner experience: cogito; ergo sum—"I am thinking; therefore I exist." In the Discourse on the Method (Pt. IV) he reasons that it is inconceivable that he, the "thinking thing," does not exist. But, he continues, I saw that I could conceive (1) that I had no body, and (2) that there was no world nor place where I might be. . . . From that I knew that
I was a substance the whole essence or nature of which is to think; and that for its existence there is no need of any place, nor does it depend on any material thing; so that this "me," that is to say, the soul by which I am what I am, is entirely distinctfrom body, and even more easy to know than the latter; and even if body were not, the soul would not cease to be what it is. . . .
. . . voyant que je pouvois feindre que je n'avois aucun cors, 8c qu'il n'y avoit aucun monde, ny aucun lieu ou je fusse . . . je connu de la que j'estois une substance dont toute I'essence ou la nature n'est que de penser, & qui, pour estre, n'a besoin d'aucun lieu, ny ne depend d'aucune chose materielle. En sorte que ce Moy, c'est a dire, I'Ame
258 Illinois Classical Studies, XI par laquelle je suis ce que je suis, est entierement distincte du cors,
& mesme qu'elle est plus aisee a connoistre que luy, 8c qu'encore qu'il ne fust point, elle ne lairroit pas d'estre tout ce qu'elle est. {Disc. IV;
H-R I, 101; A-T VI, 32-33)
There we have the essence of the Cartesian logico-introspective method; his identification of the thinking subject with the soul; and the basic reason for soul's complete independence of body and consequent immortality.
The same line of reasoning is found in Meditations VI:
And although ... I possess a body with which I am intimately conjoined, yet because, on the one side, I have a clear and distinct idea of myself inasmuch as I am only a thinking and unextended thing, and as, on the other, I possess a distinct idea of body, inasmuch as it is only an extended and unthinking thing, it is certain that this I is entirely and absolutely distinct from my body, and can exist without it. Et quamvis . . . habeam corpus, quod mihi valde arete conjunctum est, quia tamen ex una parte claram & distinctam habeo ideam mei ipsius, quatenus sum tantum res cogitans, non extensa, & ex alia parte distinctam ideam corporis, quatenus est tantum res extensa, non cogitans, certum est me a corpore meo revera esse distinctum, & absque illo posse existere. {Med. VI; H-R I, 190; A-T VII, 78)
Soul, then, is for Descartes the "thinking thing" {res cogitans) with which I, the person, am identified. It is a substance, "a thinking and unextended thing . . . entirely and absolutely distinct from my body," which is another substance, "an extended and unthinking thing," as he describes them. The consequence is for him that this "I," that is, my soul, since it is entirely and absolutely distinct from my body, can exist without it. The same reasoning in extended form appears in
Meditations II (H-R I, 149-151).
Descartes identifies soul also as "mind," or "understanding" or
"reason" ("sum igitur praecise tantum res cogitans, id est, mens, sive animus, sive intellectus, sive ratio . . . ," Med. II; H-R I, 152; A-T
VII, 27). And "thinking" includes for him a range of psychic events far beyond what Aristotle would classify as functions of the rational soul, i.e., as "thought." "What is a thing that thinks?" he asks. "It is a thing which doubts, understands, conceives, affirms, denies, wills, refuses, which also imagines and feels."
Res cogitans. Quid est hoc? Nempe dubitans, intelligens, affirmans, negans, volens, nolens, imaginans quoque, &: sentiens. {Med. II; H-R
I, 153; A-T VII, 28)
Theodore Tracy, SJ. 259
In his Principles of Philosophy Descartes summarizes his position on what thought (cogitatio) is:
By the word Thought I understand all that of which we are conscious as operating in us. And that is why not alone understanding, willing, imagining, but also feeling, are here the same as thought. For if I say
I see, or I walk, I therefore am, and if by seeing and walking I mean the action of my eyes or my legs, which is the work of my body, my conclusion is not absolutely certain; because it may be that, as often happens in dreams, I think I see or walk, although I never open my eyes or move from my place. . . . But if I mean only to talk of my sensation (sensu) or my consciously seeming to see or to walk, it becomes quite true, because my assertion now refers only to my mind, which alone is concerned with my feeling or thinking that I see and I walk.
Cogitationis nomine, intelligo ilia omnia, quae nobis consciis in nobis hunt, quatenus eorum in nobis conscientia est. Atque ita non modo intelligere, velle, imaginari, sed etiam sentire, idem est hic quod cogitare. Nam si dicam, ego video, vel ego ambulo, ergo sum; & hoc intelligam de visione, aut ambulatione, quae corpore peragitur, conclusio non est absolute certa; quia, ut saepe fit in somnis, possum putare me videre, vel ambulare, quamvis oculos non aperiam, & loco non movear. . . . Sed si intelligam de ipso sensu sive conscientia videndi aut ambulandi, quia tunc refertur ad mentem, quae sola sentit si^e cogitat se videre aut ambulare, est plane certa. {Princ. Part I, IX;
H-R I, 222; A-T VIII, 7-8)
Descartes considers all the data of consciousness, then, as "thought" belonging to the soul, assuring the conscious subject of his existence.
What of the body? And the external world? Descartes is assured of their existence only through the veracity of God, the Creator, whose existence is known with a certainty second only to that of his own existence. For Descartes discovers within his consciousness the "idea of a Being who is omniscient, omnipotent, and absolutely perfect"
(". . . unam [ideam] esse entis summe intelligentis, summe potentis
& summe perfecti . . .", Princ. Part I, XIV; H-R I, 224; A-T VIII,
10). And from the fact that his mind "perceives that necessary and eternal existence is comprised in the idea which it has of an absolutely perfect Being, it has clearly to conclude that this absolutely perfect
Being exists" (". . . ita ex eo solo quod percipiat existentiam necessariam
& aeternam in entis summe perfecti idea contineri, plane concludere debet ens summe perfectum existere," Princ. Pt. I, XIV;
H-R, I, 225; A-T VIII, 10). Now the first of the Creator's attributes is that He is "absolutely true and the source of all light, so that it is evidently a contradiction that He should deceive us" (". . . summe verax, &: dator omnis luminis: adeo ut plane repugnet ut nos fal260
Illinois Classical Studies, XI lat . . . ," Princ. Pt. I, XXIX; H-R I, 231; A-T VIII, 16). Hence it follows that "the faculty of knowledge which God has given us can never disclose to us any object which is not true, inasmuch as it comprehends it . . . clearly and distinctly" ("Atque hinc sequitur
. . . cognoscendi facultatem a Deo nobis datam, nullum unquam objectum posse attingere, quod non sit verum, quatenus ab ipsa attingitur, hoc est, quatenus clare 8c distincte percipitur," Princ. Pt. I,
XXX; H-R I, 231; A-T VIII, 16). Again, "because God is no deceiver, the faculty of knowledge that He has given us cannot be fallacious" in assenting "to things that we clearly perceive" (". . . cum Deus non sit fallax, facultas percipiendi quam nobis dedit, non potest tendere in falsum . . . cum tantum ad ea quae clare percipiuntur se extendit,"
Princ. Pt. I, XLIII; H-R I, 236; A-T VIII, 21). What are some of these things "we clearly perceive"? Descartes replies: "Of this nature are mathematical demonstrations, the knowledge that material things exist, and the evidence of all clear reasoning . . . about them" ("Tales sunt Mathematicae demonstrationes; talis est cognitio quod res materiales exsistant; 8c talia sunt evidentia omnia ratiocinia, quae de ipsis hunt," Princ. Pt. IV, CCVI; H-R I, 302; A-T VIII, 328). (This is obviously a world apart from what has been called Aristotle's
"naive realism.")
Descartes asserts the existence of only two created substances^
{Princ. Pt. I, XLVIII; H-R I, 238; A-T VIII, 23): ". . . the one is intellectual things . . . pertaining to the mind or to thinking substance; the other is material things, or that pertaining to extended substance,
i.e., to body" (". . . unum est rerum intellectualium ... ad mentem sive ad substantiam cogitantem pertinentium; aliud rerum materialium, sive quae pertinent ad substantiam extensam, hoc est, ad corpus"); for we have "two clear and distinct ideas, the one of created substance that thinks, the other of corporeal substance" (". . . possumus duas claras & distinctas habere notiones, sive ideas, unum substantiae cogitantis creatae, aliam substantiae corporeae . . . ^ Princ.
Pt. I, LIV; H-R I, 241; A-T VIII, 25). Each has its principal attribute:
". . . extension in length, breadth, and depth constitutes the nature of corporeal substance; and thought constitutes the nature of thinking substance" ("Nempe extensio in longum, latum & profundum, substantiae corporeae naturam constituit; 8c cogitatio constituit naturam substantiae cogitantis," Princ. Pt. I, LIII; H-R I, 240; A-T VIII, 25).
' "By substance we can understand nothing else than a thing which so exists that it needs no other thing in order to exist" ("Per substantiam nihil aHud intelligere possumus, quam rem quae ita existit, ut nulla alia re indigeat ad existendum," Princ .
Pt. I. LI, H-R I, 239; A-T VIII, 24). Descartes clearly understands that this definition cannot be applied univocally to God and created substances.
Theodore Tracy, S.J. 261
Functions of the soul, of the body, and of the compound are described thus {Princ. Pt. I, XLVIII; H-R I, 238; A-T VIII, 23):
Perception, volition, and every mode of knowing and willing pertain to thinking substance; while to extended substance pertain magnitude, or extension in length, breadth, and depth, figure, movement, situation, divisibility into parts themselves divisible, and such. Besides these there are, however, certain things we experience . . . which should be attributed neither to mind nor body alone but to the close and intimate union that exists between the body and mind. . . . Such are the appetites of hunger, thirst, etc., and also the emotions or passions of the mind which do not subsist in mind or thought alone, as the emotions of anger, joy, sadness, love, etc.; and finally all the sensations
"
such as pain, pleasure, light and color, sounds, odors, tastes, heat, hardness, and all other tactile qualities.
Perceptio, volitio, omnesque modi tam percipiendi quam volendi, ad substantiam cogitantem referuntur; ad extensam autem, magnitudo, sive ipsamet extensio in longum, latum 8c profundum, figura, motus, situs, partium ipsarum divisibilitas, & talia. Sed & alia quaedam in nobis experimur, quae nee ad solam mentem, nee etiam ad solum corpus referri debent, quaeque . . . ab arcta & intima mentis nostrae cum corpore unione proficiscuntur; nempe appetitus famis, sitis, &:c.; itemque, commotiones, sive animi pathemata, quae non in sola cogltatione consistunt, ut commotio ad iram, ad hilaritatem, ad tristitiam, ad amorem, &c.; ac denique sensus omnes, ut doloris, titillationis, lucis
& colorum, sonorum, odorum, saporum, caloris, duritiei, aliarumque tactilium qualitatum.
We have already seen the broad outline of Descartes' physiological psychology by which soul and body were described as interacting through the nervous system, the animal spirits, and the pineal gland, the "principal seat" of the soul, where soul receives and reacts to material impulses from inside and outside the organism, and sets up physical changes relayed to the muscles that control bodily motion.
What we now appreciate, however, is that soul and body are conceived basically as two completely distinct and independent substances which somehow join to cooperate in this manner.
The body is, in fact, conceived by Descartes as a machine, created in such a way that it could exist independently of soul, operating by purely mechanical principles, principally through the vital heat centered in the heart. Descartes considered all material substances, even heat, to be composed of minute bodies or corpuscles having only those attributes he mentions,—extension in length, breadth, depth, figure or shape, movement, situation, and divisibility. The sole type of change or motion is mechanical—by impact or collision of particles,
262 Illinois Classical Studies, XI by pushing or pulling in larger structures. Descartes compares the body specifically to "a watch or other automaton (i.e., a machine that moves itself)" which is "wound up and contains in itself the corporeal principle of those movements for which it is designed along with all that is requisite for its action" (". . . une montre, ou autre automate
(c'est a dire, autre machine qui se meut de soy-mesme) ... est montee,
& ... a en soy le principe corporel des mouvemens pour lesquels elle est instituee, avec tout ce que est requis pour son action . . . ," Passions of the Soul Pt. I, Art. VI; H-R I, 333; A-T XI, 331). Unlike Aristotle,
Descartes does not consider soul to be cause of the ordinary lifeprocesses of the body "since they do not depend on thought at all"
(". . . en tant qu'ils ne dependent point de la pensee . . . ," Pass., Pt.
I, Art. IV; H-R I, 332; A-T XI, 329).
... I consider the body of a man as being a sort of machine so built up and composed of nerves, muscles, veins, blood and skin that though there were no mind in it at all, it would not cease to have the same motions as at present, exception being made of those movements which are due to the direction of the will, and in consequence depend upon the mind. . . .
... si considerem hominis corpus, quatenus machinamentum quoddam est ex ossibus, nervis, musculis, venis, sanguine & pellibus ita aptum & compositum, ut, etiamsi nulla in eo mens existeret, eosdem tamen haberet omnes motus qui nunc in eo non ab imperio voluntatis nee proinde a mente procedunt. . . . (Meditations VI; H-R I, 195; A-T
VII, 84)
Death of the body is not caused by departure of the soul; rather, the soul departs because the body breaks down, as "a watch or other machine when it is broken and when the principle of its movement ceases to act" (". . . montre, ou autre machine, lors qu'elle est rompue
& que le principe de son mouvement cesse d'agir," Passions Art. VI;
H-R I, 333; A-T XI, 331).
Soul and body chiefly interact, as we have seen, through the pineal gland, which Descartes specifies as "the portion of the brain by which the mind is immediately affected" (". . . in ea parte cerebri quae immediate mentem afficit . . . ," Med. VI; H-R I, 197; A-T VII, 87); it receives the mechanical reactions of the body and itself acts, in
Descartes words, "immediately upon the soul" (". . . immediatement contre I'ame . . . ," Passions, Art. XXXV; H-R I, 348; A-T XI, 356).
Of pain perception he says ". . . the movement [of the nerves] passing ... to the inmost parts of the brain, gives a sign to the mind, which makes it feel somewhat, to wit, pain" (". . . ille eorum motus ... ad intima cerebri pertingens, ibi menti signum dat ad
Theodore Tracy, SJ. 263 passing ... to the inmost parts of the brain, gives a sign to the mind, which makes it feel somewhat, to wit, pain" (". . . ille eorum motus ... ad intima cerebri pertingens, ibi menti signum dat ad aliquid sentiendum, nempe dolorem . . . ," Med. VI, H-R I, 197;
A-T VII, 88). Conversely, he says that when the soul "desires something, it causes the little gland to which it is closely united to move in the way requisite ..." (". . . veut quelque chose, elle fait que la petite glande, a qui elle est estroitement jointe, se meut en la fagon qui est requise . . . ," Passions, Art. XLI; H-R I, 350; A-T XI,
360).
But how does Descartes conceive these two separate and distinct substances to be "closely united"? As far as I know, his best response is contained in Meditation VI where he declares that nature, through the sensations of pain, hunger, and thirst, teaches that I am not only lodged in my body as a pilot in a vessel, but that
I am closely united with it, and, so to speak, so intermingled with it that I seem to compose with it one whole . . . these sensations of hunger, thirst, pain, etc. are in truth none other than certain confused modes of thought which are produced by the union and apparent intermingling of mind and body.
. . . me non tantum adesse meo corpori ut nauta adest navigio, sed illi arctissime esse conjunctum & quasi permixtum, adeo ut unum quid cum illo componam. . . . Nam certe isti sensus sitis, famis, doloris, &:c., nihil aliud sunt quam confusi quidam cogitandi modi ab unione & quasi permixtione mentis cum corpore exorti. {Med. VI; H-R I, 192;
A-T VII, 81)
"Intermingling" can be easily understood of two different material substances; but what does it mean when applied to the union of a material with a completely non-material substance, one incapable of physical contact or location in place? When one of his critics (Arnauld) accuses Descartes of conceiving man as "a spirit that makes use of a body" (". . . animum utentem corpore. . . ," Objections IV; H-R II,
84; A-T VII, 203), Descartes claims that his argument from the consciousness of pain, hunger, and thirst have "proved that mind was substantially united with the body" ("Nam in eadem sexta Meditatione, in qua egi de distinctione mentis a corpore, simul etiam probavi substantialiter illi esse unitam . . . ," Reply to Objections IV; H-R II,
102; A-T VII, 227-28). Though he uses the expression "substantial union" of mind and body, it cannot be understood in the Aristotelian sense of form and matter uniting to constitute a single substance, since Descartes has rejected the notion of substantial form. Another critic (Gassendi) continues to press him on the point. "For there is
264 Illinois Classical Studies, XI sine partibus commiscibilibus utrique. . . . Quaenam vero corporeae cum incorporea intelligi potest?" Objections V: H-R II, 201; A-T VII,
344). Descartes replies testily: "At no place do you bring an objection to my arguments; you only set forth the doubts you think follow from my conclusions" ("Nihil ullibi in meas rationes objicis, sed tantum dubia proponis, quae tibi ex meis conclusionibus sequi videntur,"
Reply to Obj. V; H-R II, 232; A-T VII, 389-90). Finally, when his friend Princess Elizabeth asks the same questions,—how a thinking soul could move the animal spirits—Descartes can only answer: "I may truly say that what your Highness proposes seems to me to be the question people have most right to ask me in view of my published works" ("Et je puis dire, avec verite, que la question que votre Altesse propose, me semble estre celle qu'on me peut demander avec le plus de raison, en suite des escrits que j'ay publiez," A-T III, 663; A.
Kenny, Descartes, 1968, p. 226).
There we have it, then. Two models of human nature, soul and body,—Aristotle's hylomorphism and Descartes' dualism. Each has its problems: If body and soul are united as matter and form, how do we account for the soul's apparent power to transcend matter in conceiving the non-material, the universal? How satisfy man's almost universal longing for personal survival after death? On the other hand, if soul is a thinking substance entirely independent of matter, and body a mere machine of well-coordinated material parts, how can they possibly be united and interact in a single composite organism? We can, of course, go a step further, as did La Mettrie a century after Descartes, and discard the notion of soul altogether, settling for the bleak view that all living beings, including man, are merely quasi-machines. But that view also has its problems. Perhaps most important is that we continue to search, to think about the problem of body and soul. Or at least that we continue to think. For, as Descartes points out in the second Meditation (H-R I, 151; A-T
VII, 27), "it might possibly be the case that—if I ceased entirely to think—I should likewise cease altogether to exist" (". . . nam forte etiam fieri posset, si cessarem ab omni cogitatione, ut illico totus esse desinerem"). University of Illinois at Chicago

Similar Documents

Premium Essay

Here Is an Extra Life for You.

...Aristotle Essay Adnan Ahmad Compare and contrast Aristotle‘s concept of mind with that of Descartes.   Introduction In this essay I attempt to show Aristotle’s concept of soul/mind*[1]. Then I compare and contrast it with Descartes’ concept of mind. In order to understand Aristotle’s concepts of mind, I shall consider Aristotle’s De Anima, in which Aristotle mostly concentrates on soul/mind discussion. I will examine the work of Kahn and Sorabji, who both considered Aristotle’s and Descartes’ philosophy in relation to soul and body problem. In order to compare Aristotle’s concept of mind with Descartes’, I am going to introduce Descartes’ most famous philosophical work which involves the question of mind directly, namely hisMeditations. ………………………….                        ……………………………                          ………………………………. If we look at Aristotle’s De Anima we can understand that pre-Aristotle thinkers were already concerned with corporeal and incorporeal problems. For example, for Plato soul was an ‘incorporeal’ and immortal thing, but body corporeal and mortal. The first impression we get from reading De Anima is that the mind and body problem was unsolved. Perhaps the resolved problem didn’t satisfy Aristotle. Aristotle claims that an incorporeal thing cannot exist without a corporeal thing.  Aristotle’s new theory for solving soul and body problems makes controversial debate among most post-Aristotelian philosophers. Rene Descartes was one of them who rejected the Aristotelian...

Words: 3631 - Pages: 15

Premium Essay

Descartes' Revolution

...Descartes’ Revolution René Descartes was a philosopher that lived from 1596 to 1650. Many philosophers have spent their career trying to either prove that his theories were correct or they have tried to disprove his theories. He spent his time trying to understand knowledge and how humans know what they know with his method of inquiry. He sparked a revolution in philosophy that has remained the standard to this day. Descartes can be classified as a genius, while studying philosophy he realized that Aristotle way of thinking was wrong because he spent his entire life preoccupied with the question; what is reality? Aristotle was not able to fully answer this question and for the 1400 years after Aristotle everyone in Europe focused on; what is reality and what is the mind? Unfortunately over those 1400 years the only thing Europe had to show for these studies was the windmill, ox plow, Alchemy (which proved to not be possible) and the dark ages. When Descartes realized that Aristotle teachings were very flawed he developed his method of inquiry. While doubting Aristotle he was able to figure out that the mind and body are related. He believed that if the mind and body are combined, that is what gives human beings free will. When people stopped focusing on what the earth was they were able to focus on what they were and on ways to improve their lives. When working on improving one’s self it leads to innovation and new inventions. Descartes also focused on truth. ...

Words: 602 - Pages: 3

Free Essay

Descartes' Life and Works

...Lecture 9/23 – Background to Descartes I. Introduction: Descartes’ Life and Works A. Descartes (1596-1650) 1. Born in La Haye, France in 1596. 2. 1606 – 1614 Descartes studies at the Jesuit University of La Fleche where his philosophical education would have focused on Aquinas and Aristotle – the dominant world view at the time. 3. 1616 – Received his law license. 4. 1637 – Discourse on Method 5. 1641 – Meditations on First Philosophy 6. 1644 – Principles of Philosophy 7. 1649 – Descartes moves to Sweden and tutors Queen Christina. 8. 1650 – Dies in Sweden in 1650. B. Descartes revolutionizes philosophy in two main ways. 1. In terms of epistemology, Descartes explores important issues via the first person point of view. He asks, “What can I from my own subjective point of view know about myself and the world around me.” This approach dominates philosophy after Descartes. 2. Descartes will also transform the way in which we think about substance. C. Descartes is a pivotal figure in the history of ideas since he writes at a time when the world is changing in important ways. The Meditations is a much discussed work. 1. Renaissance (1350-1550) 2. Reformation (Beginning in the First Half of the Sixteenth Century) ...

Words: 1427 - Pages: 6

Premium Essay

Rene Descartes

...Rene Descartes When the term modern philosophy is mentioned, it is usually to make a distinction from ancient and medieval philosophy therefore it does not only mean the philosophy of the 21st century, it means, the philosopher Rene Descartes. Therefore in practice what the term, modern philosophy means is, philosophy from Descartes onwards. He was best known for his quote, ‘Cogito ergo sum’ (I think, therefore I am). Descartes was born on March 31st 1596, in La Haye, a small town in France. He was educated in classics, logic and the philosophy of Aristotle at the Jesuit college of Henri IV in La Fleche. After he graduated he studied at the University of Poitiers, obtaining his law license in 1616. He then joined the army and during his spare time he studied mathematics (Gaukroger and Hall, 1995). In 1619, he experienced the series of powerful dreams, which influenced him greatly in his pursuit of science and knowledge, and he acknowledged this ass his focal point of his life (Gaukroger and Hall, 1995). Descartes spent time in various parts of Europe before he settled in Dutch Republic. He maintained his studies and lived in various places throughout the Republic. During this time, he began his writing career, and he started to publish his new works that would revolutionize mathematics and philosophy, these works included the world, meditation of first philosophy, principles of philosophy and passions of the soul. His mathematical theories provided the basis for the...

Words: 1045 - Pages: 5

Premium Essay

Homework

... Sophie’s World: p. 105 “Philosopher and Scientist” – p. 116 1. Know the order of students from Socrates to Aristotle. Socrates, Plato, Aristotle (Oldest to Youngest). 2. Know the difference between Plato’s forms and the world. ------------------------------------------------------------------ 3. Know how Aristotle thought of forms. “Form” is each things specific characteristics. Example: A chicken’s form is fluttering, crackling and laying eggs. (What is does). But if the chicken dies, the form no longer exists. Aristotle believed there was purpose in everything that happened in nature. 4. Know how Aristotle comes to “know” something. Logic. 5. Know what Aristotle meant by “substance”. “Substance” is what things are made of. When the chicken dies, the only thing remaining is that it’s substance. 6. Know what Aristotle meant by “causes” and know the different kinds of cause. “Cause” is how something came to happen, and Aristotle cared about purpose as well. Material Cause, Efficient Cause and Final Cause. 7. Know the difference between sufficient and necessary causes. If you have (A) is sufficient for (B) it means that every time you have (A) you will have (B), without exception. If you have (A) is necessary for (B) it means that every time you have (B) you will have (A), without exception. 8. Know how Aristotle viewed happiness. “Man can only achieve happiness by using all his abilities and capabilities.” He said there were...

Words: 858 - Pages: 4

Free Essay

Omnar

... 9. Define dialectic 10. Virtue in Greek philosophy. Explain the meaning of knowledge in Socrates’s ethics 11. Explain “Eutyfro dilemma” 12. Plato’s theory of ideas: ideas and sensual objects – differences and similarities 13. Plato’s theory of ideas: the conception of participation 14. Plato’s theory of ideas: the allegory of the cave 15. Plato’s theory of ideas: the ideal state 16. Aristotle: syllogisms 17.Hylomorphism: substance and its components 18. Aristotle: the four causes: what is the sense of final cause? 19. Aristotle: the theory of virtue (Golden Mean) 20. Aristotle: what does it mean to be a political animal? 21. The existence of God: ontological argument as formulated by St. Anselm 22. The existence of God: ontological argument as formulated by Descartes (deceitful demon and “Matrix”) 23. The existence of God: Pascal’s wager 24: Theodicy: how to explain suffering and injustice? 25. Descartes: the Cartesian method – its main assumptions and functions 26. Descartes: cogito and the mind/body problem 27. The theory of substance: monism and monistic theories 28. The theory of substance: pluralism and pluralistic theories 29. What is the...

Words: 348 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

History of Psychology

...History of Psychology Katrena Taylor PSY/310 October 11, 2011 History of Psychology Psychology at one time was just a branch of philosophy, it was 1000’s of years before it was known to be a formal discipline. It evolved from “ideas” of early philosophers into a science of its own. Centuries ago Western Philosophers began the formation of psychology as a branch of philosophy, but explored the subject in a more rationale scientific way throughout the years. Just as it took centuries for the science of psychology to implore, it was and still is, developing into the 19th century. Beginnings of Psychology Wilhelm Maximilian Wundt was a German physiologist, physician, philosopher, professor, and psychologist. He is well known as the “father of experimental psychology (Bringmann, 1975). At the University of Leipzig he founded the very first formal laboratory for psychological research in 1879. In the laboratory the exploration basically of the subconscious and conscience mind began. He studied the nature of religious beliefs and how they”conditioned” human behavior. Wundt also researched the damaged parts of the brain; he started identifying mental disorders and abnormal behaviors (Bringmann, 1975). With this research Wundt was able to separate psychology as a science from philosophy. In 1881, Wundt created the first journal for psychological research. Wundt also wrote, Principles of Physiological in 1874, which was very...

Words: 1003 - Pages: 5

Premium Essay

Rene Descartes Research Paper

...Rene Descartes “I think, therefore I am” is one of the most well-known statements by Rene Descartes. Descartes was a French philosopher and mathematician of the Renaissance. The Renaissance was period of time the emphasised the importance of education. Humanism, the study of classical texts to help understand your own time was developed during this era. The renaissance encouraged exploration of the New World, and many scientific discoveries were made at that time. Descartes was an influential man that would revolutionize the way of thinking for many Europeans with his contributions to the era. Descartes revolutionized the way of thinking for Europeans because of his invention of the Cartesian Coordinate, his work in optics, and his influence...

Words: 1189 - Pages: 5

Free Essay

Compare and Contrast

...Epistemological Comparison and Contrast Dorothy M. Conner University of Phoenix Epistemological Comparison and Contrast Descartes ' Theory of Knowledge Rene Descartes is one of the most renowned rationalists of the modern age who asserts that knowledge can be obtained by means of reason. He claims that in the acquisition of knowledge one should be able to distinguish what is true and what is false. This leads to his opposition against the idea of experience as a source of knowledge As Descartes claims it, one should not rely on experience as a source of knowledge for the reason that experience is deceptive as how a person's sensory organs can bring deception with the way he or she perceives things (i.e. the bending of the pencil when submerged in water). Descartes furthers states that because of this fallibility of experience one cannot really arrive at true knowledge by merely being dependent on what he or she perceives through experience. As a result of Descartes treatment of experience, he suggests that to attain genuine and true knowledge, one should defer his or her judgment on things that are represented to him or her by experience unless such are presently proven to be unquestionable. Descartes is a perplexity in many ways. Although he has a refreshing distaste for the voodoo logic of his day steeped as it was in the questionable science of the scholastic movement, when provoked he was equally capable of skewing his own thinking when confronted with the entrenched...

Words: 1088 - Pages: 5

Premium Essay

History of Psychology

...who made great contributions are; Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and Descartes. Many believe that Aristotle may have contributed more to prescience psychology than any other individual. Aristotle was the first to believe in the importance of empirical observations. Observation is something that is widely used today in research and by many individuals in the field of psychology. He was also a great contributor to defining intellect and obtaining knowledge. (Daniels, 1997). Socrates believed that the goal of life was knowledge. Much of his knowledge was gained through questioning other philosophies. His biggest focus was on the problems related to human existence therefore he is thought of by some as the first existential philosopher. (Daniels, 1997). He was also the first to speak of the word “psyche” which he defined as ones type of intelligence and personality. (Daniels, 1997). Socrates had great influence on Plato. Plato was a rationalist who’s ideas led Freud and Marx to call their beliefs “scientific”. He also influenced many researchers, some of which are still influenced today. Rene Descartes is another very important figure in the history of psychology. In fact he is sometimes “considered the father of modern philosophy, mathematics, physiology and psychology.” (Goodwin, 2008). According to some historians the year of 1543 is the year in which modern science came to be. About 70 years later Descartes set out to begin making his contributions, He set out...

Words: 301 - Pages: 2

Premium Essay

History of Psychology

...who made great contributions are; Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and Descartes. Many believe that Aristotle may have contributed more to prescience psychology than any other individual. Aristotle was the first to believe in the importance of empirical observations. Observation is something that is widely used today in research and by many individuals in the field of psychology. He was also a great contributor to defining intellect and obtaining knowledge. (Daniels, 1997). Socrates believed that the goal of life was knowledge. Much of his knowledge was gained through questioning other philosophies. His biggest focus was on the problems related to human existence therefore he is thought of by some as the first existential philosopher. (Daniels, 1997). He was also the first to speak of the word “psyche” which he defined as ones type of intelligence and personality. (Daniels, 1997). Socrates had great influence on Plato. Plato was a rationalist who’s ideas led Freud and Marx to call their beliefs “scientific”. He also influenced many researchers, some of which are still influenced today. Rene Descartes is another very important figure in the history of psychology. In fact he is sometimes “considered the father of modern philosophy, mathematics, physiology and psychology.” (Goodwin, 2008). According to some historians the year of 1543 is the year in which modern science came to be. About 70 years later Descartes set out to begin...

Words: 787 - Pages: 4

Premium Essay

Cognitive Psychology

...Cognitive Psychology PSY/360 April 7, 2011 Cognitive Psychology Psychology possesses several branches. One of these branches is cognitive psychology. Like biological psychology, this branch also seeks knowledge that potentially unlocks wonders of the mind. However, cognitive psychology focuses on the mental processes from an internal source not physically apparent. Whereas technology provides efficient methods for which to scan a brain and the activity therein, studying the mind is still yet to uncover mysteries behind thought. Studying the mind involves observation of behavior and of the environment but determining reason for thought in general is still out of reach. Inabilities to determine unobtainable conclusions do not slow the pursuit of knowledge, for the study of conscious thought continues. This paper includes an understanding of what cognitive psychology, as well as information regarding four essential milestones contributing to the development of cognitive psychology. In addition, this paper also focuses on the importance of behavioral observation. Comprehending Cognitive Psychology Cognitive psychology currently focuses on three main human characteristics. The first characteristic is the ability to perceive. Perception is important because this is the process in which an individual interprets the immediate environment as well as changes, situations, and interactions within it. The second characteristic...

Words: 1131 - Pages: 5

Premium Essay

Alexander The Great Cosmopolitanism

...All in all, Aristotle’s philosophy made an astounding influence. In fact, it is in Aristotle’s Philosophy that Alexander the Great, which the former tutored in 347 BCE, laid down the foundations of the latter’s empire. Throughout Alexander’s rule, the influence of Aristotle, his mentor, can be seen in the former’s skillful and diplomatic handling of difficult problems throughout his career. When Alexander became a king, he had set forth on a Persian expedition to expand his empire. Perhaps, it is the experience of the encounter between people’s that played a huge role in the development of the idea of cosmopolitanism, the idea that a man is a citizen of the world. “Aristotle's writings, like Plato's, have influenced virtually every avenue...

Words: 1571 - Pages: 7

Premium Essay

History of Psychology

...exploring the development of the science of psychology during the 19th century. Ancient philosophers is the where history bagan in the field of psychology. Although these philosophers all had an intrerst with how the human mind and body works, they all had different interests, studies and experiments. They may have shared similar standpoints but some had different views. Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle were three Greek ancient philosophers who had a major influence on psychological thought. “Know thyself” one of Socrates’ most famous quotes. This quote was used to emphasize how important it is to be aware of one’s self. Personal reflection and self- examination are key factors in psychology. Plato was one of Socrates’ most prized students. He believed that our perception was inaccurate most of the time. To obtain knowledge he believed that one should depend on their thought and reason. Aristotle, Plato’s student, believed that we could gain information through careful obeservstion using our senses. He believed that our knowledge should be gained based on experience in life. Aristotle believed that people are naturally drawn to finding...

Words: 488 - Pages: 2

Premium Essay

Cognitive Psychology

...Cognitive Psychology CandiseDiaz Cognitive Psychology Psychology possesses several branches. One of these branches is cognitive psychology. Like biological psychology, this branch also seeks knowledge that potentially unlocks wonders of the mind. However, cognitive psychology focuses on the mental processes from an internal source not physically apparent. Whereas technology provides efficient methods for which to scan a brain and the activity therein, studying the mind is still yet to uncover mysteries behind thought. Studying the mind involves observation of behavior and of the environment but determining reason for thought in general is still out of reach. Inabilities to determine unobtainable conclusions do not slow the pursuit of knowledge, for the study of conscious thought continues. This paper includes an understanding of what cognitive psychology, as well as information regarding four essential milestones contributing to the development of cognitive psychology. In addition, this paper also focuses on the importance of behavioral observation. Comprehending Cognitive Psychology Cognitive psychology currently focuses on three main human characteristics. The first characteristic is the...

Words: 1118 - Pages: 5