Free Essay

Color Phenomenology

In:

Submitted By gregbaccay2012
Words 9873
Pages 40
Color Relationalism and Color Phenomenology∗
Jonathan Cohen†
Color relationalism is the view that colors are constituted in terms of relations between subjects and objects. The most historically important form of color relationalism is the classic dispositionalist view according to which, for example, red is the disposition to look red to standard observers in standard conditions (mutatis mutandis for other colors).1 However, it has become increasingly apparent in recent years that a commitment to the relationality of colors bears interest that goes beyond dispositionalism (Cohen, 2004; Matthen, 1999, 2001, 2005; Thompson, 1995).2 Accordingly, it is an important project for those interested in the metaphysics of color to sort through and assess different forms of color relationalism. There is, however, a powerful and general cluster of objections that has been thought by many to amount to a decisive refutation of any and all forms of color relationalism. Although this idea has been developed in a number of ways, the basic thought is that relationalism — qua theory of color — is at odds with the manifest evidence of color phenomenology, and that this clash between theory and data should be resolved by giving up the theory.3
∗ The material in this paper overlaps with parts of chapter 6 of my forthcoming book, The Red and the Real: An Essay on Color Ontology. I am grateful to members of the audience at SPAWN, where a version of this paper was presented, and particularly to Bence Nanay, David Chalmers, Andr´ Gallois, and Brian McLaughlin, for extremely useful criticism and advice that has improved e the paper considerably. † Department of Philosophy, University of California, San Diego, 9500 Gilman Drive, La Jolla, CA 92093-0119, joncohen@aardvark.ucsd.edu 1 Many find versions of this position in the writings of Galileo, Boyle, Newton, and Locke. More recently, forms of dispositionalism have been defended by McGinn (1983); Peacocke (1984); Johnston (1992). Note that not all accounts of color that invoke dispositions count as relationalist in my sense. For example, the “physicalist”accounts of Byrne and Hilbert (1997a, 2003); Tye (1995, 2000) treat colors as dispositions to affect (not subjects, but) light; such accounts are not forms of relationalism, since they deny that colors are constituted in terms of relations to subjects. 2 For the record, I favor a form of relationalism according to which colors are identical to the functional roles of disposing their bearers to look certain ways to certain subjects in certain conditions. For example, I hold that red for S in C is the functional role of disposing its bearers to look red to S in C, green for S in C is the functional role of disposing its bearers to look green to S in C (and so on). For defense of this view, see Cohen (2009). 3 Most of the objections of this type that occur in the literature are directed against dispositionalist theories; this is unsurprising, since the elaboration and defense of non-dispositionalist forms of relationalism is a relatively recent development. However, it seems clear that many of the arguments I’ll be considering are applicable to forms of relationalism other than dispositionalism. It is

1

My aim in this paper will be to defend relationalism from three versions of this phenomenological objection. I’ll begin, in §1, by responding to the accusation that ordinary color phenomenology presents colors as non-relational, and thereby clashes with color relationalism. Next, in §2, I’ll consider a worry to the effect that, were color relationalism true, colors would be invisible — hence, that there would be no color phenomenology at all. Finally, in §3, I’ll consider the objection that color relationalism clashes with the evidence of phenomenology by predicting that our color experiences should be partly about experience itself. I’ll conclude that none of these objections ultimately provides a compelling reason for giving up color relationalism.

1

Do Colors Look Relational?

Of course, color relationalism is an extremely controversial thesis about the metaphysics of color. However, a surprisingly wide range of writers with a surprisingly wide range of other commitments have been sympathetic to the allegation that color relationalism fails on phenomenological grounds. Specifically, many have held that — with notable exceptions such as the colors of holograms and highly glossy materials — ordinary phenomenology presents colors as non-relational properties of their bearers (Dancy (1986, 181), Armstrong (1987, 36), Boghossian and Velleman (1989, 85), Averill (1992, 556), Johnston (1992, 226–227), Yablo (1995, 489–490), McGinn (1996, 543–544), Tye (2000, 152–153), Chalmers (2006, 56), Gibbard (2006, 10), Averill and Hazlet (2008), and Johnston (2002, chapter 5)).4 Thus, whatever successes they have along other dimensions, relationalist accounts are accused of representing colors in a (relational) way that unacceptably clashes with the phenomenology of color. McGinn puts this anti-relationalist worry eloquently (and in a refreshingly explicit way) in the following passage: . . . when we see an object as red we see it as having a simple, monadic, local property of the object’s surface. The color is perceived as intrinsic to the object, in much the way that shape and size are perceived as intrinsic. No relation to perceivers enters into how the color appears; the color is perceived as wholly on the object, not as my goal in this paper to defend relationalism generally speaking, rather than this or that particular form of relationalism; consequently, while it will sometimes smooth exposition for me to treat the objections in the anti-dispositionalist form in which they come, I’ll also comment on the potential extension of my defenses to other forms of relationalism as well. I should also mention that there is a second type of more theoretical but still broadly phenomenal objection to relationalism that I won’t consider in this paper. This second type of objection alleges not that color relationalism conflicts with the phenomenological data, but rather that relationalism cannot be combined with the best metaphysical theories of color phenomenology without leading to incoherence or infinite regress (for a classic articulation of this objection, see Boghossian and Velleman, 1989). I develop and respond to this concern in Cohen (2009, chapter 6). 4 This objection presupposes that color phenomenology has an intentional content. I am assuming that that presupposition is correct. However, the objection does not presuppose (and I won’t presuppose) that color phenomenology can be reductively understood in terms of its intentional content, or that it supervenes on its intentional content.

2

somehow straddling the gap between it and the perceiver. Being seen as red is not like being seen as larger than or to the left of. The “color envelope” that delimits an object stops at the object’s spatial boundaries. So if color were inherently relational, . . . then perception of color would misrepresent its structure — we would be under the illusion that a relational property is nonrelational. Contraposing, given that perception is generally veridical as to color, colors are not relational (McGinn, 1996, 541–542).5 However, the phenomenological objection under consideration raises an important puzzle, some answer to which is presupposed by all of the authors mentioned above, and whose solution is necessary before we can properly assess the objection: how, if at all, could phenomenology represent the relationality or non-relationality of color properties in the first place?6 To see the force of the question we are pondering, notice that corresponding
5 In the course of (usefully) attempting to elaborate this complaint, McGinn fleshes out the worry by reference to four distinct features: simplicity, monadicity, locality, and intrinsicness. But it seems to me that the challenges posed by some of these features are more serious than those posed by others. For example, the claim that phenomenology is at odds with various forms of color relationalism in representing colors as simple seems false; on the contrary, phenomenology represents (surface) colors as having at least the dimensions of hue, saturation, and lightness (Clark, 1993), and perhaps more. (It is a topic of ongoing controversy how many dimensions are needed to encode color appearances.) On the other hand, if phenomenology represents colors as monadic, so do dispositionalism and other forms of color relationalism. These theories claim that colors are constituted in terms of relations to various relata, but those relata have determinate values and so are not open variables in need of saturation by individuals. Just as to the left of is non-monadic, and to the left of Sally is not, so, too, disposed to look x to y in z is non-monadic (if x , y and z are variables), but disposed to look red to S in C is non-monadic (if S and C pick out determinate individuals/viewing conditions relative to a context). I take the most serious of McGinn’s worries here to concern the allegation that phenomenology does, and relationalism does not, represent colors as intrinsic (given, perhaps, the view that intrinsic properties are those shared by perfect duplicates (Lewis, 1986)). Accordingly, this is the form of the objection I’ll be concerned with in what follows. Note also that leading “physicalist” theories of color such as those of Byrne and Hilbert (1997a, 2003); Tye (1995, 2000) that treat colors as dispositions to affect light — theories that (as noted above) don’t count as relational for present purposes — also have the consequence that colors fail to be intrinsic in Lewis’s sense, and so face versions of the present objection. 6 One might hope to answer this puzzle by accepting the thesis Johnston (1992) calls Revelation: “The intrinsic nature of canary yellow is fully revealed by a standard visual experience as of a canary yellow thing” (223). This principle would have it that undergoing color phenomenology brings with it concomitant knowledge of the intrinsic nature of the colors it represents. (It should be noted that Johnston ultimately denies Revelation, although he takes it as a regulative constraint that is part of commonsense conceptions of color, and should be respected as much as possible. Proponents of Revelation-like views include Russell (1912, 47), Strawson (1978, 224), Campbell (1993, 178ff), and arguably Moore (1903, 7, 10).) Unfortunately, this is an unsatisfactory response to our puzzle. For one thing, nothing has yet been said to motivate Revelation, and it would seem that motivating this thesis is at least as challenging as answering the original puzzle. Second, knowledge of the intrinsic nature of a property may not reveal whether that property is constituted in terms of a relation to subjects (although this will turn on one’s theory of intrinsicness). But if not, then even the truth of Revelation would do nothing to explain how undergoing color phenomenology would confer upon one evidence about the relationality of colors.

3

claims about the phenomenology of non-color properties can seem somewhat bizarre. For some non-color properties (e.g., being water, being square, or being a table) it just seems implausible that phenomenology represents their constitution (a fortiori, their relationality or non-relationality) at all. On the contrary, discerning the essences of such properties seems to require much more than simple phenomenology. The additional information needed might be empirical (as in the case of natural kind properties), mathematical (as in the case of shape properties), psychological (as, arguably, in the case of artifact properties), or something else; but in no such case would the simple enjoyment of ordinary phenomenology suffice.7 The relevance of phenomenology to discerning essence is somewhat less clear for paradigmatic relational properties, such as velocity properties.8 However, I take it that it is our best theories of the world, and not phenomenology, that tells us that each velocity property is constituted in terms of a relation to a reference frame. (Were this not true it would be hard to explain how non-relativistic conceptions of velocity properties could have had the long scientific life that they did; after all, Newton presumably enjoyed motion phenomenology roughly as often as Einstein did.) One might conclude from these considerations either that (i) phenomenology is entirely non-committal about the relationality or non-relationality of velocity properties or else that (ii) phenomenology represents velocity properties as non-relational but we take phenomenology to be revisable in the light of further (broadly empirical) inquiry. On either reading of the situation with velocity properties, however, it does seem clear that there is some story that needs to be told about when and how phenomenology can have any bearing on questions about property constitution in general, and on questions about the relationality or non-relationality of the properties it represents in particular. As a way of approaching an answer to this question, let us continue to reflect on the case of velocity properties to see what lessons can be gleaned. If, as I have suggested, phenomenology is not the route to discerning the relationality of velocities, then what is? While the answer surely involves a complicated mix of empirical observation and ratiocination, one ingredient of this mix, in particular, strikes me as highly relevant to the answer: comparison. A strong clue to the relationality of velocities — and a clue that Einstein (1905) relies on crucially in arguing for the relationality of motion properties — is that their exemplification by a particular object depends on variations in the reference frame chosen. That is, comparison reveals that the velocity of x with respect to frame F1 is different from the velocity of x with respect to frame F2 . Now, it must be emphasized that this sort of evidence is only one piece of a complex
7 While some have maintained that phenomenology exhausts the essence of certain kinds of phenomenal properties such as being in pain (Kripke, 1980), this conclusion won’t generalize to color properties unless, implausibly, the latter are construed as phenomenal as well. 8 In saying that velocity properties are relational I mean that velocity properties are constituted in terms of relation to reference frames — something I take to be an uncontroversial lesson of 20th century physics. Note that this claim is prima facie compatible with (but by no means makes compulsory) the view, defended by Tooley (1988), that velocities are intrinsic to individual instants.

4

chain of reasoning leading to the conclusion that velocity properties are relational; in particular, this evidence won’t establish that conclusion unless we can rule out (by some combination of evidence and ratiocination) the alternative hypothesis that one or the other otherwise incompatible representations of x’s velocity (one representation in F1 , the other in F2 ) is erroneous. But if that alternative hypothesis is rejected, then comparative data of the sort we are considering provides strong (but defeasible) support for the view that velocities are relational. I now want to suggest that this lesson can be generalized more widely. The idea would be that, for other target families of properties, too, comparative evidence of this sort is crucial (but, as always, defeasible) in testing for the relationality or non-relationality of its members. Namely, as in the motion case, we can test for the relationality of a property (in a family of properties) to a parameter by altering the value of that parameter and checking to see whether this change has the effect of modifying which (if any) member of our target family is exemplified. To see the power and correctness of this method, consider its application to a few test properties. The method correctly predicts that shape properties are not constituted in terms of a relation to viewing angle, for example, because square objects (say) continue to be square regardless of the angle from which they are viewed (or so we think). The same method correctly predicts that the “meteorological” properties we ascribe by saying ‘it’s raining’ or ‘it’s sunny’ are constituted in terms of a relation to location and time, since their applicability is a function of those two parameters. Likewise, as Shoemaker (1994, 254–255) notes, this test shows that being heavy is constituted in terms of a relation to a (potential) lifter and gravitational field. This comparative test, then, delivers the right verdicts about a range of properties other than colors. Of course, phenomenology seems largely irrelevant to the application of the comparative test to the cases we’ve considered so far; all that that test demands is that we assess whether an object persists in its exemplification of a target property as we modify the value of some parameter. But phenomenology could play a role in this test if it should turn out that the object’s exemplification of the target property is somehow essentially tied to phenomenology. To see what this amounts to in a concrete case, consider the so-called shimmering or unsteady colors such as those on the backs of CDs or in holograms — colors that are often put forward as examples of colors that (unusually) are represented phenomenally as being relational (e.g. Johnston, 1992, 226–227).9 Applying the comparative test to these unsteady colors (with respect to the parameter of viewing angle) means testing to see whether an object maintains or varies its unsteady color as it is viewed from different viewing angles. Crucially, however, in this case, we assess the object’s unsteady colors from each viewing angle primarily (perhaps only) by attending to the way in which it is phenomenally presented when viewed from that angle. Here, then, applica9 The distinction between “unsteady” and “standing” colors is made by Johnston (1992, 141), who attributes it to Rossotti (1983, chapters 3–4).

5

tion of the comparative test means engaging in comparative phenomenology. And what the test reveals is that unsteady colors are relational (constituted in terms of a relation to viewing angle). That is so because even very slight variations in viewing angle of the kind that we engage in — often involuntarily — in ordinary perceptual circumstances show up in the phenomenal representation of their colors: by very slight and often involuntary motions, we obtain in quick succession a visual representation of x’s color when viewed from angle α and a visual representation of x’s color when viewed from angle β, and find that these two representations differ phenomenally. These considerations involving comparative phenomenology explain three related facts. First, that unsteady colors behave this way explains the widely held view (even among those who take steady colors to be non-relational) that the unsteady colors of surfaces are constituted in terms of a relation to the viewing conditions under which they are perceived. Second, the fact that the conditions under which we view shimmering surfaces gives us (often involuntarily) the comparative information we need to carry out the comparative test explains why the latter view is widely held in the first place — typical perceptual circumstances provide us with the needed data, and once the data are in our possession, it is hard to avoid drawing the obvious conclusion from them. Third, and even more significantly, these considerations address our initial question by showing how phenomenology can speak to the relationality or non-relationality of a target property. Namely, when phenomenology provides our evidence about the exemplification of that property, then comparative phenomenological data collected across variations in relevant parameters can serve as grounds for inferences about the relationality/non-relationality of the target property. But now I want to suggest that the so-called steady colors meet this criterion, so the comparative phenomenological test just used to assess the relationality of the unsteady colors should be applicable to the steady colors as well. The significant difference between the two is that, in the case of steady colors, we need systematic psychophysical comparison, rather than just the conditions of typical perception, to bring out the relevant comparative data. In particular, we need to compare the visual representation of x’s color when viewed by S1 in conditions C1 against the visual representation of x’s color when viewed by S2 in conditions C2 . Now, it turns out that ordinary, everyday color phenomenology doesn’t provide the materials needed for these kinds of comparisons all by itself. For one thing, ordinary phenomenology can’t (by itself) facilitate comparisons between subjects S1 and S2 . For another, what distinguishes “steady” colors from shimmers is that one can easily obtain a phenomenal representation of x’s color for oneself in C1 without obtaining a phenomenal representation of x’s color for oneself in C2 . This means that testing for the relationality of “steady” colors will require more than the unsystematic, ordinary phenomenology we undergo outside the psychophysics lab.10 Or, in the words of Janet Levin,
10 Boghossian

and Velleman (1989) miss this point, and therefore apply (what seems to me to be)

6

Ordinary perception of color may seem to reveal colors to be simple monadic properties, just as a quick glance may seem to reveal an object with color highlights to be an object that is “steadily” striped. But in both cases, the “glances” are too quick to be definitive, given the sorts of experiences required for making the distinction; in neither case can these judgments be expected to reflect what perception in the proper circumstances would in fact reveal (Levin, 2000, 157). On this matter I agree strongly with Levin: isolated and momentary phenomenal presentations (“glances”) are insufficient to bring out the relationality of both so-called steady and unsteady colors, because the comparative information needed to make their relationality apparent is more than such isolated and momentary phenomenal presentations make available. Now, one respect in which my thinking about these matters differs from Levin’s is that she focuses on interpersonal comparisons as the key to bringing out phenomenally the relationality of colors. Since interpersonal phenomenal comparisons are, arguably, never made available by ordinary perception (by itself), Levin concludes that the conditions under which colors would be phenomenally represented as relational, “alas, are not available even in a lifetime of normal perceptual experience” (157). But, in my view, phenomenal evidence of the relationality of color can, in principle, be marshaled from intrapersonal phenomenal comparisons — comparisons that are, plausibly, more readily available in ordinary perception. In any case, it seems clear that the most direct and systematic methods for making the relevant comparisons (whether interpersonal or intrapersonal) are those used in the psychophysics lab. That is, the systematic comparisons we need are made available by precisely the kinds of psychophysical methods frequently exploited in motivating relationalism (e.g., see Cohen (2004)). Namely, these methods allow us to ask S1 and S2 to make phenomenal matching judgments of x’s color relative to various perceptual conditions, and thereby to compare the phenomenal representation of x’s color for S1 in C1 against the phenomenal representation of x’s color for S2 in C2 . Significantly, carrying out those comparisons shows that the pair of phenomenal representations differ as a function of the subject and the perceptual circumstances. As in other applicathe wrong criterion to test whether phenomenology presents colors as relational/dispositional: If colours looked like dispositions, however, then they would seem to come on when illuminated, just as a lamp comes on when its switch is flipped. Turning on the light would seem, simultaneously, like turning on the colours; or perhaps it would seem like waking up the colours, just as it is seen to startle the cat. Conversely, when the light was extinguished, the colours would not look as if they were being concealed or shrouded in the ensuing darkness: rather, they would look as if they were becoming dormant, like the cat returning to sleep. But colours do not look like that; or not, at least, to us (Boghossian and Velleman, 1989, 85). In fact, if Boghossian’s and Velleman’s observations are correct, then they show only that (nonshimmering) colors are not constituted in terms of relations to parameters whose values shift under ordinary conditions of perception by a single subject. And, of course, this falls far short of showing that colors are not relational/dispositional.

7

tions of the comparative method, this finding gives (defeasible) support for the idea that our target property (in this case, x’s color) is constituted in terms of a relation to the parameters under consideration (in this case, the subject and the perceptual circumstance). What all of this shows, I think, is that phenomenology represents the steady colors of tables and chairs as relational to exactly the extent and in exactly the way that it represents the unsteady colors of CDs and holograms as relational. This can be taken in two ways, depending on how expansively we think about what phenomenology amounts to. If phenomenology is restricted to single, isolated, representations that are not integrated with ratiocinative reflection (Levin’s “glances”), then I think phenomenology reveals neither steady nor unsteady colors as being relational. On the other hand, if we take a broader view of what phenomenology includes — in particular, if we take within the purview of phenomenology both systematic (psychophysical) and ordinary comparisons between phenomenological representations, together with inferences reached on the basis of such comparative data, then it seems to me that phenomenology reveals both unsteady and steady colors to be relational. Why, then, have many theorists agreed that phenomenology differs in what it reveals about steady and unsteady colors, and therefore endorsed the phenomenological objection against color relationalism? Part of the answer, I suspect, is that have been unclear between the narrower and broader understandings of phenomenology spelled out above. As noted, ordinary perceptual circumstances make it difficult to avoid carrying out comparative phenomenology with respect to “unsteady” colors, and I believe this fact has prevented many from seeing that they were engaging in comparisons (or ratiocination based on these comparisons) at all. And this has encouraged many to believe that phenomenology in the narrower sense reveals the relationality of unsteady colors, when, in my view, it is phenomenology in the broader sense that is responsible. In effect, then, such thinkers have gone looking for phenomenological evidence in the wrong place. This, in turn, has led to the erroneous expectation that, were so-called steady colors relational, then phenomenology understood in the narrower sense would also reveal this fact. As it happens, it does not. Moreover, since the manipulations required to bring out the relationality of steady colors do not occur “all by themselves” in ordinary perception, subjects are left without the phenomenological evidence they would need to come to a suitable conclusion on this matter. But since they lack the requisite evidence, and also (wrongly) believe they would possess such evidence if it existed, they have concluded (wrongly) that steady colors are phenomenally represented as non-relational. Which is to say that, after having looked for phenomenological evidence in the wrong place, such thinkers have compounded their error by mistaking an absence of evidence for evidence of absence. This diagnosis is supported by the observation that exactly the same sort of error can arise in the case of non-color properties that are less controversially relational. Thus, to use Shoemaker’s example, the natural limitations on the comparative evidence available to us in assessing the heaviness of objects can erroneously lead us (at least initially, until we seek out comparative evidence 8

and take it into account) to think that phenomenology represents being heavy as non-relational. For, at least initially, I might ascribe or forebear the property being heavy just on the basis of the narrow phenomenal episodes I undergo when I lift them, given the (relatively stable over time) strength and physical build that I happen to have, and in the context of a relatively unchanging gravitational field (it changes so little mainly because, in the course of my ordinary travel, I don’t alter significantly my distance from the center of the earth). As before, restricting myself to non-comparative phenomenological evidence of this kind will not show up the relationality of the target property; indeed, my contention is that narrow, isolated episodes of phenomenology (“glances”) neither reveal being heavy to be relational nor to be non-relational. Someone who (wrongly) expected her narrow phenomenology to represent all and only relational properties as being relational would wrongly conclude on the basis of her narrow phenomenology that being heavy is not relational. But, as before, this would be an erroneous conclusion reached by taking into account the wrong kind of phenomenological evidence (viz., narrow rather than broad phenomenology). I take these considerations to show that there is both a good sense in which phenomenology can speak to the question of whether colors (steady and unsteady alike) are relational or not, and another good sense in which phenomenology won’t speak to that question. The sense in which it will is the sense in which phenomenology includes systematic comparisons of the sort made available by psychophysical methods, combined with ratiocination. The sense in which phenomenology will have nothing to say about the relationality or otherwise of colors is one in which phenomenology is restricted to introspection on isolated, momentary experiential episodes. Of course, the narrower brand of phenomenology won’t reveal colors as relational — but that is only because it is unsuited to discovery of relationality where it exists at all. In contrast, employing the broader conception of phenomenology leads to the conclusion that colors are relational. On neither, conception, however, are we justified in concluding that phenomenology represents colors as being nonrelational.

2

Are Relational Properties Visible?

A second potentially powerful and generalizable phenomenal objection against relational theories of color builds on the platitudinous claim that colors are visible — i.e., that instances of colors (if not color properties themselves) can be seen. However, critics have alleged, (instances of) dispositional/relational properties are not the sorts of things that can be seen, even if it is allowed that their relata can be seen. Rather, these critics urge, the exemplification of such dispositional/relational properties by particulars is something we infer, possibly on the basis of the exemplification of other properties that we do see.11 If
11 Obviously this objection presupposes the viability of a distinction between what we see and what we infer. While this presupposition is controversial (see Churchland, 1979; Fodor, 1984), it’s appropriate for me to grant it for concessive reasons (if no other).

9

that worry is correct, then relational accounts of color would entail the absurd conclusion that colors are not visible.12 Once again, this objection is given a particularly clear exposition by McGinn (1996), who frames the issue in terms of the question of what can be a direct object of the seeing relation: When you look at an object you do not see (de dicto) its dispositions to act in certain ways in certain circumstances, but you do see what color it is. Here, of course, I mean direct object perception, not just seeing-that — seeing the property itself, not merely seeing that it is instantiated. You may see that something is soluble by watching it dissolve, but you do not see its solubility — that property itself. You can see the manifestation of the disposition, and you may also see the categorical basis of the disposition in the object’s molecular structure, but your eyes do not acquaint you with the property of being disposed to dissolve. . . . And now the point about colors is that they enter the very content of primitive visual experience, being part of how objects appear, but dispositions of whatever kind cannot themselves enter visual content in this way (McGinn (1996, 540); cf. Mackie (1976, chapter 1)). Although McGinn presents this objection in the first instance as a reason for rejecting the dispositionalism he had endorsed earlier (McGinn, 1983), the threat he poses clearly generalizes to other forms of relationalism as well: if colors are possible direct objects of seeing, then any relationalist account of color will be threatened by the worry that relational properties — as opposed to their relata — cannot be direct objects of seeing. Now, one possible line of resistance to this argument turns on a thought developed by McGinn himself, in his earlier defense of dispositionalism (McGinn, 1983, 133–135). This line of resistance turns on the idea that ‘sees’ introduces a highly intensional context — one where sameness of sense and reference does not guarantee intersubstitutability salva veritate.13 If true, this claim would explain why ‘I see redness’ could be true while ‘I see the disposition to look red’ could be false even if (as per some forms of dispositionalism) ‘redness’ and ‘the disposition to look red’ are alike not only in reference but also in sense. Unfortunately, this answer strikes me as unconvincing. For while I take it to be extremely plausible that (the phenomenal use of) ‘looks’ introduces such a highly intensional context (see § 3), it seems (at least, to my linguistic intuition)
12 Mark Johnston attempts to extend the absurdity here by arguing that, if we didn’t see (instances of) colors, we would not see objects (Johnston, 1992, note 1). This argument, however, is unconvincing as it stands: even if we could not see instances of colors, it is left open that we could (veridically) see objects by undergoing color illusions — i.e., we could see objects by seeing that they look colored, even if it turns out that we never see any veridical instances of colors (say, because nothing is colored, as per color irrealism). Once again, it is worth noticing that a version of the worry considered here for relationalism arises for those non-relational theories of color that identify colors with dispositions to affect light. 13 A version of this response to the objection is also considered by McLaughlin (2003), although he doesn’t put much weight on it.

10

not only that the context created by ‘sees’ is not so highly intensional, but that it is extensional; but if so, then the proposal under consideration is just inapplicable to the case at hand. On the other hand, I do not believe that the present objection against relationalist views is decisive. In particular, I do not see a reason for accepting the premise that colors, if dispositions or otherwise constituted in terms of relations to perceivers, are ipso facto not suitable for being the direct objects of seeing. (For ease of expression, in what follows I’ll discuss this point only in terms of dispositional versions of relationalism, but I hope it is clear that the response can be generalized.) At least in McGinn’s presentation above, the case for this conclusion rests almost entirely on the analogy with the dispositional property solubility. Although this is controversial, I am prepared to spot McGinn the assumption that dispositions such as solubility and fragility are not — or, are not directly — objects of the seeing/looking relation.14 However, this might be thought to overlook relevant differences between dispositions, some of which can be the direct object of seeing, and some of which cannot. The reason we should take this possibility seriously, it seems to me, is that the dispositions identified with colors by dispositionalists — in dramatic contrast to paradigm dispositions like solubility or fragility — have visual experiences as their manifestations. And the reason this matters to the question about whether dispositions can be seen is that it is plausibly constitutive of seeing a disposition to look red (as it might be) that one undergoes the visual experience that is the manifestation of that very disposition. In this spirit, McDowell asks, “What would one expect it to be like to experience something’s being such as to look red, if not to experience the thing in question (in the right circumstances) as looking, precisely, red?” (McDowell (1985, 112) (cf. Levin, 2000, 154–155)). We can buttress this thought by locating it against the following sufficient condition for property seeing: S sees property P if, by visually attending to an exemplification of P by x, S is (non-deviantly) caused to undergo a visual experience that represents x as exemplifying P . Now, a couple of remarks about this condition for property seeing are in order.15 First, the condition explicates seeing a property in terms of seeing one of its instances. I take this to be appropriate, since I assume we causally interact with properties only in virtue of causally interacting with their instances. Second, some readers might object to the idea that we see properties (/their instances) by visually attending to them, and instead hold that we visually attend to these things only by seeing them. While there may be some understanding of visual attention that substantiates this objection, I am here understanding visual attention as an early and encapsulated mechanism that selectively allocates the resources of the visual system to objects/regions; so understood, it seems to me that property seeing should depend on visual attention rather than vice versa. Third, the condition is only offered as a sufficient condition, rather than a necessary and sufficient condition, for property seeing. One respect in which it fails to be a necessary
14 For 15 Thanks

dissent on this point, see Anscombe (1981); Cartwright (1989). to Brian McLaughlin for urging me to clarify my thoughts on these matters.

11

condition involves misrepresentation: in cases where, by visually attending to an exemplification of P by x, S is non-deviantly caused to undergo a visual experience that (mis-) represents x as exemplifying Q, I am inclined to hold that S nonetheless sees property P . Finally, many philosophers have worried that dispositions — as opposed to their categorical bases — can’t cause their manifestations. If they are right about this, then the present account won’t allow that subjects can see dispositional properties (hence, given dispositionalism about color, won’t allow that subjects see colors), since it won’t be possible for dispositions to look red (for S in C) to cause objects to look red (for S in C). This concern, of course, is only as good as the underlying assumption that dispositions are unable to cause their manifestations. But I think the extant arguments for this assumption, which turn mostly on Kim-style considerations about the threat of causal overdetermination by multiple factors each causally sufficient for the outcome (Kim, 1989a,b, 1993a, 1998), are unconvincing.16 The thought I’d like to pursue, then, is that the dispositionalist’s colors can (unlike fragility) be seen in this sense of property seeing because the dispositionalist’s colors (unlike fragility) have visual experiences as their manifestations. For example, suppose a ripe tomato exemplifies the disposition to look red, and suppose the viewing conditions are propitious; then precisely in so far as the disposition manifests itself, it will be true that by visually attending to the tomato’s redness I am (non-deviantly) caused to undergo the particular visual experience that represents the tomato as red.17 For this reason, it is plausible for a dispositionalist to hold that the occurrence of the disposition’s manifestation is constitutive of my seeing the tomato’s (by hypothesis, dispositional) color property. Of course, this won’t make it the case that we see all dispositions; in particular, and as desired, this account won’t make it the case that we see dispositions whose manifestations are not visual experiences, for they won’t meet the sufficient condition for property seeing given above (although this allows that we might succeed in seeing those properties or their instances in some other way — the condition is only a sufficient condition for property seeing). If, for example, a vase exemplifies fragility, even if I attend to this state of affairs, the
16 The literature contains a large number of responses to such Kim-inspired arguments. One common response involves the allegation that the argument overgeneralizes and (unacceptably) threatens the possibility of causal explanation in terms of the kinds of special sciences quite generally speaking (Fodor (1989, 138–141); van Gulick (1992, 325); Baker (1993, 77); Burge (1993, 102); but see Kim (1997) and Kim (1998, 77–87, 112–120)). A different line of response, brought out by Loewer (2007), is that, contrary to what proponents of such arguments often maintain, the multiple factors involved (here, the base property and the disposition) are not causally sufficient for the outcome (here, the manifestation of the disposition). Indeed, nothing less than the total state of the universe at a time is causally sufficient for the outcome; but there seems no reason to fear causal overdetermination by a pair of factors each of which is not causally sufficient for the outcome. 17 The claim here is not that we see the disposition by seeing the visual experience that is the manifestation of the disposition — indeed, I deny that we see our visual experiences except in highly abnormal circumstances (such as those involving invasive neurosurgery). Rather, the claim is that the visual experience itself (when it is appropriately caused by something to which we are visually attending) is the manifestation of the disposition, and that undergoing (rather than seeing) such a visual experience constitutes seeing the disposition (in the direct object sense at issue).

12

manifestation of the disposition leaves entirely open whether I’ll undergo a visual experience that represents the vase’s fragility. This is because, in this case, the disposition’s manifestation (here, a shattering) is independent of the occurrence of any visual experience at all. What all this shows, I suggest, is that the unsuitability of some dispositions to be objects of the seeing relation is compatible with the claim that colors, if dispositions, can be the objects of the seeing relation. And now we should notice that forms of the response I am recommending are also available to non-dispositionalist relationalists for whom the current threat about the invisibility of colors arises. Although the details of the analysis will differ depending on the form of relationalism on offer, the key insight on which the answer depends is general: namely, it is that we can understand how a relational property R is seen by a subject S if the relevant relation eventuates in a visual experience in S that represents R’s exemplification. I conclude, then, that, contrary to the present worry, color relationalists can endorse the platitudinous view that colors are visible.

3

Phenomenology about Phenomenology?

According to dispositionalism and several other forms of color relationalism, colors are constituted in terms of relations to subjects that involve those very subjects undergoing phenomenal experiences. For example, suppose we hold the form of dispositionalism according to which red for S in C = the disposition to look red to S in C. If, (plausibly) something’s looking red to S in C requires that S undergo a phenomenal experience of some sort, it would seem that what it is to be red involves constitutively an episode of phenomenology. Now suppose S has a phenomenal experience that represents x as red. Assuming dispositionalism, this means that her phenomenal experience has as its content that x is disposed to look red. And, given what we’ve said above, this means that the phenomenal experience has as its content something like this: that x is disposed to produce in S phenomenal experiences of a certain kind. This means that, assuming the truth of dispositionalism (and the relatively uncontroversial claim that x looks red to S only if S undergoes a certain phenomenal experience), phenomenal experiences of x’s being red will have as part of their content a claim about phenomenal experience. Moreover, and for the same reasons, an analogous conclusion follows from non-dispositionalist forms of relationalism according to which the relation between subjects and objects that constitutes color properties is one that requires the subject to undergo a certain phenomenal experience. All of these relationalist views have the consequence that color phenomenology represents phenomenology (inter alia). However, some have found this consequence implausible. Reflecting on their own color phenomenology, they simply do not find that their experiences have any representational commitments about phenomenology. Thus, McGinn complains that, 13

I do not have experiences of experiences when I see something red. When I see an object as red I see it as having a property; I do not see any sensations that might be occurring in perceivers. . . . My experience type does not enter its own content. (McGinn, 1996, 542). According to this thought, my ordinary experience of a ripe tomato, as it might be, represents the fruit’s size and shape, but is just not committed in any way to any claims about visual phenomenology. One might be sympathetic to this claim because one shares the oft-cited “Moorean” intuition to the effect that phenomenal experience always represents distal objects and their properties rather than mental entities and their properties (see Harman, 1990). Alternatively, one might take the weaker view that, at least in ordinary, non-reflective settings, the contents of phenomenal experiences (or phenomenal color experiences in particular) do not involve mental entities, a fortiori do not involve phenomenal experiences. Either way, once again, the worry is that relationalism (in at least some of its forms) seems to have an entailment that is at odds with the data of ordinary color phenomenology. It is important to note that the worry under consideration is not that the invocation of phenomenology in a phenomenal representation results in a theory that is viciously circular or otherwise objectionable.18 That is to say, the difficulty is not merely that the invocation of phenomenology in a phenomenal content is itself somehow incoherent. It is that the invocation of phenomenology as the content of the particular sort of phenomenal representations at issue is, it is claimed, erroneous as a description of that content. How should relationalists respond to the objection now before us? In my view, they should respond by rejecting the alleged phenomenal datum on which it is based. In particular, relationalists should reject the claim that color phenomenology does not represent properties whose nature is explicated in terms of phenomenal experience. What the relationalist should claim is that such experience-involving properties are constituents of the contents of color experience, but that their experience-involving natures are hidden from those who undergo color phenomenology, even when those subjects attend carefully to their experiences. That is, a subject who undergoes color phenomenology thereby has an experience that represents a color property whose nature involves color phenomenology as a component; but in undergoing that phenomenal episode, the (experience-involving) nature of the represented color property is not made apparent to the subject even upon careful reflection on her experience. This response, of course, presupposes that it is possible to represent in one’s phenomenal experience properties whose essence is not known to one; but I think that that commitment is perfectly reasonable and well-precedented. After all, even if you and I know the essence of water, presumably Homer was able to enjoy — and carefully attend to — water phenomenology despite lacking this piece of knowledge. Had someone proposed to Homer that water is H2 O, it would not have been reasonable for him to object that water couldn’t
18 For

a response to that worry see Cohen (2009, chapter 6).

14

have hydrogen as an essential constituent on the grounds that his water phenomenology failed to disclose the involvement of hydrogen upon careful attention. That this is so should not be thought to depend solely on Homer’s failing to have a concept of hydrogen. For it seems that someone who knows quite a lot about hydrogen might also reflectively undergo water phenomenology without thereby coming to know the constitution of water(cf. RodriguezPereyra, 2002, 93–94). Again, it would be unreasonable for such a subject to object that water couldn’t have hydrogen as an essential constituent on the grounds that her water phenomenology failed to disclose the involvement of hydrogen upon careful attention. Likewise, then, it seems to me that it would unreasonable to object to the identification of being red to S in C and the disposition to look red (to S in C) on the grounds that one’s red phenomenology fails to disclose the involvement of visual phenomenology upon careful attention. Another way to put the foregoing is to say that phenomenal occurrences of ‘looks’ in locutions of the form ‘x looks red (to S in C)’ create highly intensional contexts — contexts within which substitution of extensionally (or even analytically) equivalent expressions is not truth-preserving (cf. McGinn, 1983, 134ff).19 Thus, although to be wet just is to be covered in a certain way with H2 O, it is illegitimate to infer from ‘x looks wet’ to ‘x looks to be covered in a certain way with H2 O’. Or, again, although to be humorous just is to be disposed to cause characteristic amusement reactions in appropriately situated cognizers, it is illegitimate to infer from ‘x looks humorous’ to ‘x looks disposed to cause characteristic amusement reactions in appropriately situated cognizers’. So, too, the failure of the inference from ‘x looks red (to S in C)’ to ‘x looks appropriately related to a (certain type of) phenomenal experience’ should not be taken to impugn the color relationalist’s identification of color properties with experience-involving essences. I claim, then, that careful reflection on one’s color phenomenology by conceptually competent subjects can fail to disclose the nature of the properties that are constituents of the contents of those experiences. Experience of colors does not amount to an unmediated, acquaintance-like connection with the colors.20 This explains why, as I suggested in §1, isolated episodes of color phenomenology must be supplemented by (sometimes extensive) comparison and ratiocination before they can teach us about the nature of colors. Color phenomenology does relate us to the colors, but it is no substitute for the hard, broadly empirical, work necessary for determining how colors are constituted.
19 I think this is so because color experiences (like water experiences) present the properties that are constituents of their contents under modes of presentation. Proponents of non-relationalist theories of colors (e.g. Tye, 1995, 133) have sometimes held this view as well (although Tye (2000, 56–57) later repudiated it). As Tye points out, if there are modes of presentation involved, they should be the kinds of modes of presentation that are available to infants and non-human animals (assuming, plausibly, that things can look colored to such creatures). And this gives some reason — depending on one’s theory of concepts, to be sure — for denying that the modes of presentation in question are conceptual. However, I see no reason that they would have to be conceptual; instead, one might regard them as perceptual (non-conceptual) modes of presentation. 20 For reasons discussed in note 6, this claim can be accepted even by those who endorse Revelation.

15

Of course, saying this means accepting that the identity statement linking colors and experience-involving relations to subjects is, at best, a posteriori. I am prepared to accept this conclusion: I hold that broadly empirical support, rather than simple phenomenal experience together with armchair reflection, is necessary to defend color relationalism. Consequently, unlike many other color relationalists, I deny that color relationalism is an a priori thesis. In any case, it seems to me that the absence of phenomenal evidence of experience-involving elements in the color properties one represents phenomenally cannot be taken as evidence of the absence of such elements in the natures of colors. But since the objection we have been considering in this section turns on treating our phenomenal evidence as just such a criterion, it is unsuccessful as a complaint against color relationalism.

4

Conclusion

For many writers, the most important shortcomings of relationalist accounts of color are phenomenological. While they (sometimes) acknowledge its other virtues, these writers allege that color relationalism presents colors in a way that conflicts with the way in which color phenomenology presents colors, and that the only intellectually virtuous response to this clash is to reject the offending theory rather than the data. However, I have argued in this paper, the phenomenological objections pressed against relationalism by its critics are unconvincing. Once we make clear just what and how color phenomenology can and cannot tell us about the nature of color properties, it turns out that phenomenal data support, rather than detract from, the case for relationalism. I conclude that color phenomenology is not the stumbling block for color relationalism that many have held it to be.

References
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1981). Causality and determination. In G. E. M. Anscombe, editor, Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind: Collected Papers, Volume II, pages 133–147. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis. Armstrong, D. M. (1987). Smart and the secondary qualities. In P. Pettit, R. Sylvan, and J. Norman, editors, Metaphysics and Morality: Essays in Honour of J. J. C. Smart. Basil Blackwell, Oxford. Reprinted in Byrne and Hilbert (1997b), 33–46. Averill, E. W. (1992). The relational nature of color. The Philosophical Review, 101(3), 551–588. Averill, E. W. and Hazlet, A. (2008). A problem for relational theories of color. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Forthcoming.

16

Baker, L. R. (1993). Metaphysics and mental causation. In Heil and Mele (1993), pages 75–95. Boghossian, P. A. and Velleman, J. D. (1989). Colour as a secondary quality. Mind, 98, 81–103. Reprinted in Byrne and Hilbert (1997b), 81–103. Burge, T. (1993). Mind-body causation and explanatory practice. In Heil and Mele (1993), pages 97–120. Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D. R. (1997a). Colors and reflectances. In A. Byrne and D. R. Hilbert, editors, Readings on Color, Volume 1: The Philosophy of Color, pages 263–288. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D. R., editors (1997b). Readings on Color, Volume 1: The Philosophy of Color. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Byrne, A. and Hilbert, D. R. (2003). Color realism and color science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26(1), 3–64. Campbell, J. (1993). A simple view of color. In J. Haldane and C. Wright, editors, Reality, Representation, and Projection. Oxford University Press, New York. Reprinted in Byrne and Hilbert (1997b), 177–190. Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Chalmers, D. (2006). Perception and the fall from eden. In T. S. Gendler and J. Hawthorne, editors, Perceptual Experience, pages 49–125. Oxford University Press, New York. Churchland, P. M. (1979). Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Clark, A. (1993). Sensory Qualities. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Cohen, J. (2004). Color properties and color ascriptions: A relationalist manifesto. The Philosophical Review, 113(4), 451–506. Cohen, J. (2009). The Red and The Real: An Essay on Color Ontology. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Forthcoming. Dancy, J. (1986). Two conceptions of moral realism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 60, 167–187. ¨ Einstein, A. (1905). Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter Korper. Annalen der Physik, 17, 891–921. Fodor, J. A. (1984). Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, 51(1), 23–43. Fodor, J. A. (1989). Making mind matter more. Philosophical Topics, 17, 59–79. Reprinted in Fodor (1990), 137–159. 17

Fodor, J. A. (1990). A Theory of Content and Other Essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Gibbard, A. (2006). Moral feelings and moral concepts. In R. Schafer-Landau, editor, Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 1, pages 195–215. Clarendon Press, Oxford. van Gulick, R. (1992). Three bad aruments for intentional property epiphenomenalism. Erkenntnis, 36, 311–331. Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. volume 4, pages 31–52. Ridgeview Publishing Company, Atascerdo, California. Heil, J. and Mele, A., editors (1993). Mental Causation. Oxford University Press, New York. Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221– 263. Reprinted in Byrne and Hilbert (1997b), 137–176. Johnston, M. (2002). The manifest. Unpublished ms., Princeton University. Kim, J. (1989a). Mechanism, purpose, and explanatory exclusion. In J. E. Tomberlin, editor, Philosophical Perspectives 3, Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory, pages 77–108. Ridgeview Publishing, Atascadero, California. Reprinted in Kim (1993b), 237–264. Kim, J. (1989b). The myth of nonreductive materialism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 63, 31–47. Reprinted in Kim (1993b), 265–284. Kim, J. (1993a). The nonreductivist’s troubles with mental causation. In J. Heil and A. Mele, editors, Mental Causation, pages 189–210. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Reprinted in Kim (1993b), 336–357. Kim, J. (1993b). Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge University Press, New York. Kim, J. (1997). Does the problem of mental causation generalize? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 97, 281–297. Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental Causation. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Originally given as the 1996 Townsend Lectures. Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Levin, J. (2000). Dispositional theories of color and the claims of common sense. Philosophical Studies, 100, 151–174. Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Basil Blackwell, Oxford. 18

Loewer, B. (2007). Mental causation, or something near enough. In B. McLaughlin and J. Cohen, editors, Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, pages 243–264. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford. Mackie, J. L. (1976). Problems from Locke. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Matthen, M. (1999). The disunity of color. The Philosophical Review, 108(1), 47– 84. Matthen, M. (2001). Our knowledge of colour. In J. Macintosh, editor, Naturalism, Evolution, and Intentionality, pages 215–246. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Supplementary volume 27. Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, Doing, and Knowing: A Philosophical Theory of Sense Perception. Oxford University Press, Oxford. McDowell, J. (1985). Values and secondary qualities. In T. Honderich, editor, Morality and Objectivity: A Tribute to J. L. Mackie, pages 110–129. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. McGinn, C. (1983). The Subjective View: Secondary Qualities and Indexical Thoughts. Oxford University Press, Oxford. McGinn, C. (1996). Another look at color. The Journal of Philosophy, 93(11), 537–553. McLaughlin, B. (2003). The place of color in nature. In R. Mausfeld and D. Heyer, editors, Colour Perception: Mind and the Physical World, pages 475– 502. Oxford University Press, New York. Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica. The University Press, Cambridge. Peacocke, C. (1984). Colour concepts and colour experiences. Synthese, 58(3), 365–81. Reprinted in Rosenthal (1991), 408–16. Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance Nominalism. A Solution to the Problem of Universals. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Rosenthal, D. (1991). The Nature of Mind. Oxford University Press, New York. Rossotti, H. (1983). Color: Why the World Isn’t Grey. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Russell, B. (1912). The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford University Press, London. Shoemaker, S. (1994). Self knowledge and ‘inner sense’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, 249–314. Reprinted in Shoemaker (1996), 201–268. Shoemaker, S., editor (1996). The First-Person Perspective and Other Esays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Strawson, G. (1978). ‘Red’ and red. Synthese, 78, 193–232. 19

Thompson, E. (1995). Colour Vision: A Study in Cognitive Science and the Philosophy of Perception. Routledge, New York. Tooley, M. (1988). In defense of the existence of states of motion. Philosophical Topics, 16, 225–54. Tye, M. (1995). Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, Color, and Content. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Yablo, S. (1995). Singling out properties. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 477–502.

20

Similar Documents

Premium Essay

Exploration of a Professional Journal Article in Psychology

...Exploration of a Professional Journal Article in Psychology Lestia Reese John Lynch Psychology of Adjustment March 03, 2013 1The purpose of the article of descriptive phenomenological study was to identify and describe the essential meaning structure in the experience of postpartum depression (PPD). 2They interviewed four women diagnosed with major depression and analyzed the data with Giorgi’s descriptive phenomenological method. Their analysis revealed two essential meaning structures of PPD. The first structure describes the mother as throw into a looming, dangerous world, coupled with a restricted, heavy body that hindered her attunement to her baby. Tormented by anxiety, guilt and shame, she tried to deal with her pain by analytical reflection and social isolation. The second structure describes sudden lapses into intense feelings of alienation from the self, the baby, and from the social and material world. With a distorted primordial self-awareness, the mother no longer felt that she existed as herself in the world. 1PPD involves a temporary collapse of fundamental structures of consciousness, that is, how they experience self, body, the social world, and time. These structures become more or less deformed, reorganized in a new interconnected gestalt, which sustains and strengthens itself if not identified and treated. Their subjects lived their postpartum depression in different ways and in different contexts. One essential meaning structure encompassed three...

Words: 758 - Pages: 4

Free Essay

Philosophical Arguments Aganst God

...SARTRE AND DENNETT ARGUMENTS AGAINST GOD NAME: INSTITUTION: Sartre arguments In the first phase, the philosophical career of Jean Paul Sartre lays emphasis on the construction of a philosophy of existence known as existentialism. Existentialism considers human nature condition as a critical philosophical problem and in which this problem can be shared through ontology (Douglas, & George, 2003). Sartre’s philosophy is explained through his ontology in which he defines two types of reality, which lie beyond our conscious experience: the being of the object of consciousness and that of consciousness itself. He argued that the object of consciousness exists in a non-rational and independent way as in-itself while consciousness is the consciousness of something concerning something else, and it is nigh possible to understand it within one's conscious experience: it exists as "for-itself." A fundamental feature of consciousness is its negative power that human experience nothing less and in which this power is also at work on the self (Douglas, & George, 2003). According to Sartre Jean-Paul (2003), God does not exist and does not exist neither on logical or rational grounds. Be it one believes His existence or not largely depends on the strength of his argument. Many scholars and philosophers commonly feel that Sartre Jean-Paul existentialism is an irrational counterpoint to the enlightenment. Sartre Jean-Paul, at least, gave reasons for his conclusions. He argued that everything...

Words: 504 - Pages: 3

Premium Essay

Philisophy

...Jean-Paul Sartre 1905-1980 Sartre questions the radical determinism and materialism of the nineteenth century. Emerging from the World Wars in Europe, Sartre wonders what is wrong with the world. Looking for an alternative to determinism, Sartre will not hearken back to Christian metaphysics, but take Husserl’s intentionality and Heidegger’s concern for Being. Sartre is an atheistic existential writer that is concern with freedom and responsibility. He was awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1964 but refused it because it appeared to him as a petty bourgeois honor. Most of the characteristics we associate with Existentialism are from Sartre. His analysis of human nature congealed during the years in France of the German occupation. He found the French collaboration and their refusal to take responsibility for wrongdoing abysmal and to join “The Resistance.” Their excuses included: appeals to innocence: “I didn’t start the war;” appeals to impotence: “What could I as one person do;” appeals to the “herd” mentality: Everyone else did it;” appeals to self-preservation: “I was looking out for myself; appeals to emotions: “I was afraid.” Yet these excuses seemed hollow and hypocritical. Thus, his philosophy can be best summarized as “no excuses!” He famously said harshly, “We always get the war we deserve.” In another way, we always get the life we deserve. Against all such excuses, Sartre argued that we are never determined, that we are “absolutely free.” This...

Words: 542 - Pages: 3

Premium Essay

Reaction Paper - Carl Rogers

...COMM S237 JOI Instructor: Gail Haynes Paper composed by: Vanessa Villefort Email: Vanessa.Villefort@edu.uni-graz.at Reaction Paper Experiences in Communication – Carl R. Rogers Everyone has different and unique experiences with communication. The psychologist Carl R. Rogers shares his experiences with communication in Chapter 1 of his book A Way of Being and by doing so provides major understandings of communication to the reader. Having read through the chapter thoroughly, I would like to follow Rodgers advice and “check what [he] says against [my] own experience and decide as to its truth or falsity for [me].” (439) In the following part I will try to make up my own mind by comparing his experience to mine. First of all, Rogers mentions the importance of hearing someone and also to be heard by someone. With hearing he refers to the process of truly listening to someone and that is not just listening to the words but also to the thoughts, the feeling tones, the personal meaning and meaning below the conscious intent of the speaker. Once people feel that someone is deeply hearing them they become relieved and more open. This feeling of being understood by another person lets people often bear their heart to that specific person which in turn makes them more open for the process of change (440). However, truly hearing someone is not an ability everyone possesses. It is a difficult process, since it requires the listener to be open and free of prejudices but also not...

Words: 1118 - Pages: 5

Free Essay

Philosophical Arguments Aganst God

...SARTRE AND DENNETT ARGUMENTS AGAINST GOD NAME: INSTITUTION: Sartre arguments In the first phase, the philosophical career of Jean Paul Sartre lays emphasis on the construction of a philosophy of existence known as existentialism. Existentialism considers human nature condition as a critical philosophical problem and in which this problem can be shared through ontology (Douglas, & George, 2003). Sartre’s philosophy is explained through his ontology in which he defines two types of reality, which lie beyond our conscious experience: the being of the object of consciousness and that of consciousness itself. He argued that the object of consciousness exists in a non-rational and independent way as in-itself while consciousness is the consciousness of something concerning something else, and it is nigh possible to understand it within one's conscious experience: it exists as "for-itself." A fundamental feature of consciousness is its negative power that human experience nothing less and in which this power is also at work on the self (Douglas, & George, 2003). According to Sartre Jean-Paul (2003), God does not exist and does not exist neither on logical or rational grounds. Be it one believes His existence or not largely depends on the strength of his argument. Many scholars and philosophers commonly feel that Sartre Jean-Paul existentialism is an irrational counterpoint to the enlightenment. Sartre Jean-Paul, at least, gave reasons for his conclusions. He argued that...

Words: 508 - Pages: 3

Free Essay

Influence of the Father on His Child

...Assignment 1: Exploration of a Professional Journal Article in Psychology Title: The Role and Influence of the Father on his Child Anthony Hunt Professor Carolyn Bird Psy 100 This research article reviews the effects of the father’s influence on his child. It involves interpretative phenomenological analysis of eight participants and the recurrence of information provided in case notes of three men and five women. This research is based on philosophical discipline originated by Edmund Husserl (1913). Husserl developed the phenomenological method to make possible a descriptive account of the essential structures of the directly given. Phenomenology emphasizes the immediacy of experience, the attempt to isolate it and set it off from all assumptions of existence or causal influence and lay bare its essential structure. (Encyclopedia Britannica, 2012) During my research I have gathered from this information why a father’s personality and behavior may effect a child’s social and emotional adjustment. Particularly, how children obtain and maintain healthy relationships with others in their future. The purpose of this research is to examine the role of the father and his child’s upbringing and to determine whether that role has a positive or negative effect. The findings will support the eight recurrent themes evolving from the 12 master themes of the eight participants. In accordance to the overall field of Psychology, this review relates to Chapter 8, Friendship...

Words: 1057 - Pages: 5

Free Essay

Twentieth Century

...Twentieth Century Philosopher Maria Pinelle, Treddie Knight, and Shurvell McClendon PHL/215 March 19, 2011 Leon Hallingquest Twentieth Century Philosopher INTRODUCTION - Well-known philosophers have influenced the lives for many centuries. Jacques Derrida was a twentieth century philosopher who was one of the most contemporary philosophers of modern (contemporary) times (Philosophy basics, 2011). Jacques Derrida was born on July 15, 1930, and died October 8, 2004 of pancreatic cancer. Derrida left behind a wife and two sons named Pierre and Jean. Derrida was the founder of Deconstructionism. What is Deconstructionism? IDENTIFY AND EVALUATE THE KEY CONCEPTS AND ANALYSES THAT COMPRISED THE PHILOSOPHER’S THEORIES –Deconstructionism or Deconstruction is a philosophical theory of criticism (usually of literature or film) that seeks to expose deep-seated contradictions in a work by delving below its surface meaning ("Deconstruction"). According to C. John Holcombe (2007), “Derrida has been called philosopher, anti-philosopher, literary theorist, literary subverter and intellectual joker. But his central tenets are clear. Once we use language (speech or writing) to refer to reality, that reality is linguistically formulated and therefore indeterminate. Meaning is not something preexisting in the mind that we struggle to express. Like the main analytical schools of language philosophy from Hume onwards, and contrary to Saussure, Derrida does not regard words as the expression...

Words: 665 - Pages: 3

Free Essay

Jean Paul Sartre

...The type of philosophy Sartre’s existential metaphysics focus on includes 1st order ethical issues and focuses on analytic ethics, contrasted with analytic philosophy. This is important because when we do existential metaphysics, we don’t treat metaphysical questions as purely theoretical ones. We’re actually interested in getting a proper understanding of what we, and the world we inhabit, are like. The 1st order ethical question asks what to do or be in a certain kind of situation- Sartre uses his answer to give a picture of Human Nature. The cosmic question states: “how can one bring into one’s individual life a recognition of one’s relation to the universe as a whole, whatever that relation is?” Sartre answers this by saying that the cosmic question has no answer, but his sense is that the absence of an answer, even if we aren’t aware of that, is something palpable in our lives and needs to be addressed and we need to cope with it. His idea of human nature is really an exploration of how we should deal with the fact that there is no answer to this cosmic question. For Sartre, to understand the structure of this world as a whole, one has to understand the place consciousness has in the world. He continues to emphasize that our consciousness is what makes us distinct, makes us human. Intentionality, self consciousness, self-determination, and their interconnectedness. Firstly, let me iterate that “intentionality” is being used in a sense NOT related to one of its meanings...

Words: 1967 - Pages: 8

Free Essay

Transcendental Phenomenology and Antonioni’s Red Desert

...Transcendental Phenomenology and Antonioni’s Red Desert This essay applies the ideas associated with transcendental phenomenology to the Michelangelo Antonioni’s 1964 film Il deserto rosso, known in English as Red Desert. Aspects of western philosophy can provide a viewer with a greater appreciation of the film and its meanings. After providing a brief overview of the development of phenomenological thinking and of past interpretations of Red Desert, this essay will provide an analysis and interpretation of the film’s cinematography –specifically its colours and editing– from a phenomenological point of view. Phenomenology maintains that experience is both passive –seeing, hearing, and so on– and active –walking, running, touching, and so on. One describes experience and interprets experience by relating it to a context, which is usually social or linguistic. The word phenomenology originates with the Greek word phainomenon, which means ‘appearance.’ Phenomenology is, then, the study of appearances rather than the study of reality. In the eighteenth century, thinkers such as Immanuel Kant and Johann Fichte began to seriously consider phenomenology as a theory of appearances, and to consider it essential to acquiring knowledge. Phenomenology has its origins, certainly, with debates regarding what exists in reality and what is an illusion. John Locke believed that qualities such as colors, sounds, smells, and so on were subjective, and were not indigenous to objects...

Words: 2435 - Pages: 10

Premium Essay

Week 5 Paper

...My personal model of helping is based on my own experience with change. It is a combination of person-centered and behavioral theories that combine together to create the framework that will help me help others. I formed this viewpoint from several different areas. The first is from the different selections in our textbook. While reading the text selections I identified most with Carl Rogers' theories of therapy. Rogers' approach to let the client feel responsible for their treatment allows the client to take responsibility for the changes that they make. Person-centered therapy does not look to the past, as more Freudian therapies do. Person-centered therapy focuses on the present and asks the client to take ownership of their own wellbeing. In combination with person-centered therapy I believe that focusing on the present with a client is very important and letting the client discover their own willingness for change. Once the client decides that they have the desire to change, they then need the skills to make those changes in their life, which is where behavioral theories are implemented. Giving the client the skills to personally implement the changes is very powerful. It gives them ownership of their treatment and teaches them how to continue their recovery even after they have ended therapy. It is akin to the Chinese proverb of, "if you give a man a fish you feed him for a day. If you teach a man to fish you feed him for a lifetime" (Author unknown)...

Words: 322 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

Quick Tour Through Phenomenological Thinking in Architecture

...Architecture has become in today’s society too dependent on the visual experience. The excess of images both in quantity and speed that afflicts our society has been observed by writers and philosophers and called “the unending rainfall of images” by Italo Calvino, “image addiction” by Richard Kearney, the civilization of the image” by Roland Barthes and “the society of spectacle” by Guy Debord. The critique of the dominance of visual aspects in architecture and the excessive rationalization of the design process is the ongoing work of a group of architects that somewhat loosely adapted the principals of phenomenology to architecture. The philosophical principals were partially applied to architecture at the beginning of the twentieth century, but reappeared as a viable alternative for architectural thought as a response to modernity and have gained a following in recent times. Juhani Pallasmaa has written: “In our time, architecture is threatened by two opposite processes: instrumentalisation and aestheticisation. On the one hand, our secular, materialist and quasi-rational culture is turning buildings into mere instrumental structures. devoid of mental meaning, for the purposes of utility and economy. On the other hand, in order to draw attention and facilitate instant seduction, architecture is increasingly turning into the fabrication of seductively aestheticised images without roots in our existential experience and devoid of authentic desire of life. Instead of being...

Words: 1323 - Pages: 6

Free Essay

Major Philosophical Theories

...Comparison Essay -- Major Philosophical Theories Myria Loper PHI 105 08/23/2012 Michael Boen Comparison Essay -- Major Philosophical Theories In this easy I will talk about three of the different schools of thought; existentialism, phenomenology and hermeneutics. I will do this by comparing each school and provide examples as well as their positions. Existentialists are mainly traditional and academic philosophers. They believe the world is irrational and focus on individuals in a confrontationally state. They also have a hard time communicating, have anxiety and self-doubt. Existentialists believe that if we do not have honesty in confronting problems we can struggle with our problems. (Moore, 2011) Phenomenoligost interest their selves in essential structures found in stream conscious experience. (Moore, 2011). Phenomenoligist believe in phenomena’s; things manifest themselves on their own based on science. These philopsophers have a large impact not in the relms of philosophy, their impact has been more in theroies of science another words scientist are often referred to as phenomenoligost. An example of phenomenology is when you are looking at an object with both eyes open and it appears to be in the center of the table. You close one eye and it appears to be more to the left then to the right. The last one I will talk about is hermeneutics. Hermeneutics believe and deal with the principles of interpretation. The way individuals interact with each other and...

Words: 406 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

Phenomenology

...Phenomenology: A research tool in nursing practice Phenomenology: A research tool in nursing practice Description of the problem Nursing as a discipline and branch of science has grown tremendously over the years. The use of research, scientific inquires, evidence-based practice, and scientific validations have contributed immensely to this growth. Several disciplines such as Psychology, Sociology, Arts, and Philosophy have played major factors in the growth of nursing as a science. Science as a discipline is never static and continues its growth through the use of quantitative and qualitative research inquires. Phenomenology is a branch of philosophy that aims to utilize methodology in nursing research (Tuohy, Cooney, Dowling, Murphy, & Sixsmith, 2013). This paper will focus on the role of phenomenology as a research tool in nursing practice and the similarities between phenomenology and the views of logical positivists. Background and significance Edmond Husserl is recognized as the pioneer of Phenomenology, having introduced this movement at the beginning of the 20th century (Tuohy et al., 2013). Phenomenology as a branch of philosophy focuses on the importance of exploring the realities of life and living, it is a method of recounting occurrences as it appears to the person experiencing the occurrence (Tuohy et al., 2013). Phenomenology is described as a movement because unlike other philosophical views; it...

Words: 2211 - Pages: 9

Free Essay

Comparison Essay

...Comparison Essay N/A PHI/105 N/A N/A Comparison Essay The three main types of philosophy, also known as schools of thought, are continental, pragmatic, and analytic philosophies. With analyzing these three types of philosophy, we can compare and contrast them and see what they are and how they are used. The first school is continental philosophy. Continental philosophy is a general term, which is supplementary with the philosophical opinions that originated on the continent of England in the 20th century (Moore & Bruder, 2011). It has numerous theories for instance, there are critical theory, deconstruction, existentialism, hermeneutics, phenomenology, and structuralism (Moore & Bruder, 2011). The schools of thought accompanying continental which are the most important the two are existentialism and phenomenology (Moore & Bruder, 2011). The best known philosophers associated with continental philosophy are Martin Heidegger and Jean-Paul Sartre (Moore & Bruder, 2011). Some themes of existentialism are traditional and academic philosophies are from the uncertainties of real life, the world is irrational, and the world is absurd in the sense that there are not explanations that can be given for the way that it is. These are not all the themes for this school of thought nonetheless these are the most fascinating (Moore & Bruder, 2011). The second type philosophy is pragmatic. Pragmatic philosophy is a type of philosophy that rejects the idea that there is...

Words: 423 - Pages: 2

Free Essay

Edmund Husserl

...Edmund Husserl Husserl is the acknowledged founder of Phenomenology. Husserl thought that Phenomenology was an exact science whose main drive was to study the phenomena, or appearances of human experience. Yet, he did not thought of it as a science of facts, but rather as an a priori or eidetic science, which deal with essences, and is grounded on the absolute certainty. This sort of certainty was thought to be achieved through examination of consciousness by consciousness itself. Thus, Husserl considered consciousness the main topic for philosophy. And in examining the form of this consciousness, Husserl discovered what he called ‘the natural standpoint’. Husserl said that the world as it is actually lived by individual is the natural standpoint. Yet according to Husserl, it is possible to get behind this natural standpoint to identify an invariant intentional structure. Husserl developed a method of bracketing, which he called epoche. For example, I may look with pleasure at a blossoming apple tree. From the natural standpoint, I can see that the tree exists outside of me in space and time and that I am enjoying my physical state of pleasure. From this standpoint, moreover, there is an assumed relation between me and the apple tree. But I can suspend my judgments about the tree and perform an epoche. This bracketing moves me from a natural to a phenomenological standpoint. By no longer referring to objective existence, by applying the phenomenological instead, I have arrived...

Words: 373 - Pages: 2